|
Listen, Marxist!
By Murray Bookchin
Introductory Note: Listen, Marxist! was
written in May 1969 for circulation at what was to be the last national
SDS convention. Once the exemplification of the comparatively non-hierarchical,
decentralized and directly participatory New Left organization forms,
SDS was at that time seriously threatened by the seemingly inexorable
Old Left (and bourgeois) tendencies toward leadershp, centralism,
bureaucracy, vanguard party mentality and factional power plays.
Listen, Marxist! was written to expose those tendencies and
to indicate the direction toward a necessary alternative. But the
gangrenous poisons had already weakened the organism and SDS was
destroyed by the deciseive split which produced the expulsion of
the Progressive Labor Party (PL), the births of Weatherman (RYMI)
and Revolutionary Youth Movement (RYM) II, and the release of a
lot of women from the stranglehold of the male-defined left to find
their way into the then fledgling feminist movement.
Since that time, parts of the many-faceted movement have incorporated
some of the non-hierarchical, non-authoritarian, immediate life-style
change concepts outlined in Listen, Marxist!; the women's
libertion movement has further contributed the concepts of "consciousness
raising" and the small group process; the gay liberation movement
has shaken a lot of assumption concerning sexual and societal roles;
and the kids and youth liberation movement is getting its thing
together with unprecedented implication. A lot has changed since
Listen, Marxist! was written.
But, the general revolutionary movement in the United States (the
authoritarian Marxist-Leninist Black Panther Party and the self-serving
Socialist Workers Party as extreme examples) is still very much
weighed down by " the tradition of all the dead generations,"
adhering to "proletariat"-oriented 19th Centruty political
and organization values that, unre-examined, simply don't apply
to the lae 20thth Century world situation (if indeed they ever applied
in the 19th Century). Also, the newly-awakened American sensitivity
to racism and imperialism has led, in its exclusivity, to a neglect
of other crucial aspects of the politics of domination: sexism,
child oppression (ageism), the destruction of the planet, to name
a very few, which need to become as valued a concern to those in
revolutionary struggle. The subtle violence of our everyday lives,
as well as American imperialist violence, need to be recognized
and dealt with. A departure from the dehumanizing and impotent identification
as "workers" demands a new solidarity as people
who require social, as well as economic, control over a life whose
quality is steadily deteriorating. An examination of all our dual
roles as both oppressor and oppressed indicates a dialiectic, not
formulistic, approach to struggle. and struggle itself need to be
redefined - transcending the vicarious "support" struggle
phenomena to a direct involvement out of our own realities; transcending
the "my ideology right or wrong" mentality to a fluid
and developing liberation coscniousness; transcending alienation
in revolutionary struggle to authentic participation in a world
liberatory process.
Listen, Marixist! isn't a manual for revolution. It was
written to destroy all manuals by validating the need for revolutionary
struggle to find its own spontaneous-organic form, by
validating the capacity of all people, when unmolested
by the domination of leaders and doctrines, to find truly visionary
ways of relating to each other and to the many diverse and sometimes
conflicting world liberation struggles.
Those of us struggling for comprehensive, truly radical world revolutionary
change need Listen, Marxist! today as much as we ever
did.
-Su Negrin
All the old crap of the thirties is coming back again--the shit
about the "class line," the "role of the working
class," the "trained cadres," the "vanguard
party," and the "proletarian dictatorship." It's
all back again, and in a more vulgarized form than ever. The Progressive
Labor Party is not the only example, it is merely the worst. One
smells the same shit in various offshoots of SDS, and in the Marxist
and Socialist clubs on campuses, not to speak of the Trotskyist
groups, the International Socialist Clubs and the Youth Against
War and Fascism.
In the thirties, at least it was understandable. The United States
was paralyzed by a chronic economic crisis, the deepest and the
longest in its history. The only living forces that seemed to be
battering at the walls of capitalism were the great organizing drives
of the CIO, with their dramatic sitdown strikes, their radical militancy,
and their bloody clashes with the police. The political atmosphere
through the entire world was charged by the electricity of the Spanish
Civil War, the last of the classical worker's revolutions, when
every radical sect in the American left could identify with its
own militia columns in Madrid and Barcelona. That was thirty years
ago. It was a time when anyone who cried out "Make love, not
war" would have been regarded as a freak; the cry then was
"Make jobs, not war" -- the cry of an age burdened by
scarcity, when the achievement of socialism entailed "sacrifices"
and a "transition period" to an economy of material abundance.
To an eighteen-year old kid in 1937 the very concept of cybernation
would have seemed like the wildest science fiction, a fantasy comparable
to visions of space travel. That eighteen-year-old kid has now reached
fifty years of age, and his roots are planted in an era so remote
as to differ qualitatively from the realities of the present
period in the United States. Capitalism itself has changed since
then, taking on increasingly statified forms that could be anticipated
only dimly thirty years ago. And now we are being asked to go back
to the "class line," the "strategies," the "cadres"
and the organizational forms of that distant period in almost blatant
disregard of the new issues and possibilities that have emerged.
When the hell are we finally going to create a movement that looks
to the future instead of the past? When will we begin to learn from
what is being born instead of what is dying? Marx, to his lasting
credit, tried to do that in his own day; he tried to evoke a futuristic
spirit in the revolutionary movement of the 1840's and 1850's. "The
tradition of all the dead generations weighs like a nightmare on
the brain of the living," he wrong in The Eighteenth Brumaire
of Louis Bonaparte.
"And when they seem to be engaged in revolutionizing themselves
and things, in creating something entirely new, precisely in such
epochs of revolutionary crisis they anxiously conjure up the spirits
of the past to their service and borrow from them names, battle
slogans and costumes in order to present the new scene of world
history in this time-honored disguise and borrowed language. Thus
Luther donned the mask of the Apostle Paul, the revolution of
1789 to 1814 draped itself alternately as the Roman Republic and
the Roman Empire, and the revolution of 1848 knew nothing better
than to parody, in turn, 1789 and the tradition of 1793 to 1795....The
social revolution of the nineteenth century cannot draw its poetry
from the past, but only from the future. It cannot begin with
itself before it has stripped off all superstition in regard to
the past....In order to arrive at its content, the revolution
of the nineteenth century must let the dead bury their dead. There
the phrase went beyond the content, here the content goes beyond
the phrase."
Is the problem any different today, as we approach the twenty-first
century? Once again the dead are walking in our midst--ironically,
draped in the name of Marx, the man who tried to bury the dead of
the nineteenth century. So the revolution of our own day can do
nothing better than parody, in turn, the October Revolution of 1917
and the civil war of 1918-1920, with its "class line,"
its Bolshevik Party, its "proletarian dictatorship," its
puritanical morality, and even its slogan, "soviet power."
The complete, all-sided revolution of our own day that can finally
resolve the historic "social question," born of scarcity,
domination and hierarchy, follows the tradition of the partial,
the incomplete, the one-sided revolutions of the past, which merely
changed the form of the "social question," replacing one
system of domination and hierarchy by another. At a time when bourgeois
society itself is in the process of disintegrating all the social
classes that once gave it stability, we hear the hollow demands
for a "class line." At a time when all the political institutions
of hierarchical society are entering a period of profound decay,
we hear the hollow demands for a "political party" and
a "worker's state." At a time when hierarchy as such is
being brought into question, we hear the hollow demands for "cadres,"
"vanguards" and "leaders." At a time when centralization
and the state have been brought to the most explosive point of historical
negativity, we hear the hollow demands for a "centralized movement"
and a "proletarian dictatorship."
This pursuit of security in the past, this attempt to find a haven
in a fixed dogma and an organizational hierarchy as substitutes
for creative thought and praxis is bitter evidence of how little
many revolutionaries are capable of "revolutionizing themselves
and things," much less of revolutionizing society as a whole.
The deep-rooted conservatism of the PLP1 "revolutionaries"
is almost painfully evident; the authoritarian leader and hierarchy
replace the patriarch and the school bureaucracy; the discipline
of the Movement replaces the discipline of bourgeois society; the
authoritarian code of political obedience replaces the state; the
credo of "proletarian morality" replaces the mores of
puritanism and the work ethic. The old substance of exploitative
society reappears in new forms, draped in a red flag, decorated
by portraits of Mao (or Castro or Che) and adorned with the little
"Red Book" and other sacred litanies.
The majority of the people who remain in the PLP today deserve
it. If they can live with a movement that cynically dubs its own
slogans into photographs of DRUM pickets; if they can read a magazine
that asks whether Marcuse is a "copout or cop"; if they
can accept a "discipline" that reduces them to poker-faced,
programmed automata; if they can use the most disgusting techniques
(techniques borrowed from the cesspool of bourgeois business operations
and parliamentarianism) to manipulate other organizations; if they
can parasitize virtually every action and situation merely to promote
the growth of their party--even if this means defeat for the action
itself--then they are beneath contempt. For these people to call
themselves reds and describe attacks upon them as redbaiting is
a form of McCarthyism in reverse. To rephrase Trotsky's juicy description
of Stalinism, they are the syphilis of the radical youth movement
today. And for syphilis there is only one treatment--an antibiotic,
not an argument.
Our concern here is with those honest revolutionaries who have
turned to Marxism, Leninism or Trotskyism because they earnestly
seek a coherent social outlook and an effective strategy of revolution.
We are also concerned with those who are awed by the theoretical
repertory of Marxist ideology and are disposed to flirt with it
in the absence of more systematic alternatives. To these people
we address ourselves as brothers and sisters and ask for a serious
discussion and a comprehensive re-evaluation. We believe that Marxism
has ceased to be applicable to our time not because it is too visionary
or revolutionary, but because it is not visionary or revolutionary
enough. We believe it was born of an era of scarcity and presented
as a brilliant critique of that era, specifically of industrial
capitalism, and that a new era is in birth which Marxism does not
adequately encompass and whose outlines it only partially and onesidedly
anticipated. We argue that the problem is not to "abandon"
Marxism, or to "annul" it, but to transcend it dialectically,
just as Marx transcended Hegelian philosophy, Ricardian economics,
and Blanquist tactics and modes of organization. We shall argue
that in a more advanced stage of capitalism than Marx dealt with
a century ago, and in a more advanced stage of technological development
than Marx could have clearly anticipated, a new critique is necessary,
which in turn yields new modes of struggle, or organization, of
propaganda and of lifestyle. Call these new modes whatever you wish.
We have chosen to call this new approach post-scarcity anarchism,
for a number of compelling reasons which will become evident in
the pages that follow.
The Historical Limits of Marxism
The idea that a man whose greatest theoretical contributions were
made between 1840 and 1880 could "foresee" the entire
dialectic of capitalism is, on the face of it, utterly preposterous.
If we can still learn much from Marx's insights, we can learn even
more from the unavoidable errors of a man who was limited by an
era of material scarcity and a technology that barely involved the
use of electric power. We can learn how different our own era is
from that of all past history, how qualitatively new are the potentialities
that confront us, how unique are the issues, analyses and praxis
that stand before us if we are to make a revolution and not another
historical abortion.
The problem is not that Marxism is a "method" which must
be reapplied to "new situations" or that "neo-Marxism"
has to be developed to overcome the limitations of "classical
Marxism." The attempt to rescue the Marxism pedigree by emphasizing
the method over the system or by adding "neo" to a sacred
word is sheer mystification if all the practical conclusions
of the system flatly contradict these efforts.[1] Yet this is precisely
the state of affairs in Marxian exegesis today. Marxists lean on
the fact that the system provides a brilliant interpretation of
the past while willfully ignoring its utterly misleading features
in dealing with the present and future. They cite the coherence
that historical materialism and the class analysis give to the interpretation
of history, the economic insights that Capital provides
into the development of industrial capitalism, and the brilliance
of Marx's analysis of earlier revolutions and the tactical conclusions
he established, without once recognizing that qualitatively new
problems have arisen which never existed in his day. Is it conceivable
that historical problems and methods of class analysis based entirely
on unavoidable scarcity can be transplanted into a new era of potential
abundance? Is it conceivable that an economic analysis focused primarily
on a "freely competitive" system of industrial capitalism
can be transferred to a managed system of capitalism, where state
and monopolies combine to manipulate economic life? Is it conceivable
that a strategic and tactical repertory formulated in a period when
steel and coal constituted the basis of industrial technology can
be transferred to an age based on radically new sources of energy,
on electronics, on cybernation?
As a result of this transfer, a theoretical corpus which was liberating
a century ago is turned into a straitjacket today. We are asked
to focus on the working class as the "agent" of revolutionary
change at a time when capitalism visibly antagonizes and produces
revolutionaries among virtually all strata of society, particularly
the young. We are asked to guide our tactical methods by the vision
of a "chronic economic crisis" despite the fact that no
such crisis has been in the offing for thirty years.[2] We are asked
to accept a "proletarian dictatorship"-- a long "transitional
period" whose function is not merely the suppression of counter-revolutionaries
but above all the development of a technology of abundance--at a
time when a technology of abundance is at hand. We are asked to
orient our "strategies" and "tactics" around
poverty and material immiseration at a time when revolutionary sentiment
is being generated by the banality of life under conditions of material
abundance. We are asked to establish political parties, centralized
organizations, "revolutionary" hierarchies and elites,
and a new state at a time when political institutions as such are
decaying and when centralizing elitism and the state are being brought
into question on a scale that has never occurred before in the history
of hierarchical society.
We are asked, in short, to return to the past, to diminish instead
of grow, to force the throbbing reality of our times, with its hopes
and promises, into the deadening preconceptions of an outlived age.
We are asked to operate with principles that have been transcended
not only theoretically but by the very development of society itself.
History has not stood still since Marx, Engels, Lenin and Trotsky
died, nor has it followed the simplistic direction which was charted
out by thinkers--however brilliant--whose minds were still rooted
in the nineteenth century or in the opening years of the twentieth.
We have seen capitalism itself perform many of the tasks (including
the development of a technology of abundance) which were regarded
as socialist; we have seen it "nationalize" property,
merging the economy with the state wherever necessary. We have seen
the working class neutralized as the "agent of revolutionary
change," albeit still struggling with a bourgeois framework
for more wages, shorter hours and "fringe" benefits. The
class struggle in the classical sense has not disappeared; it has
suffered a more deadening fate by being co-opted into capitalism.
The revolutionary struggle within the advanced capitalist countries
has shifted into a historically new terrain: it has become a struggle
between a generation of youth that has known no chronic economic
crisis the culture, values, and institutions of an older, conservative
generation whose perspective on life has been shaped by scarcity,
guilt, renunciation, the work ethic and the pursuit of material
security. Our enemies are not only the visibly entrenched bourgeoisie
and the state apparatus but also an outlook which finds its support
among liberals, social democrats, the minions of a corrupt mass
media, the "revolutionary" parties of the past, and, painful
as it may be to the acolytes of Marxism, the worker dominated by
the factory hierarchy, by the industrial routine, and by the work
ethic. The point is that the divisions now cut across virtually
all the traditional class lines and they raise a spectrum of problems
that none of the Marxists, leaning on analogies with scarcity societies,
could foresee.
The Myth of the Proletariat
Let us cast aside all the ideological debris of the past and cut
to the theoretical roots of the problem. For our age, Marx's greatest
contribution to revolutionary thought is his dialectic of social
development. Marx laid bare the great movement from primitive communism
through private property to communism to its highest form--a communal
society resting on a liberatory technology. In this movement, according
to Marx, man passes on from the domination of man by nature, to
the domination of man by man, and finally to the domination of nature
by man and from social domination as such.[3] Within this larger
dialectic, Marx examines the dialectic of capitalism itself - a
social system which constitutes the last historical "stage"
in the domination of man by man. Here, Marx makes not only profound
contributions to contemporary revolutionary thought (particularly
in his brilliant analysis of the commodity relationship) but also
exhibits those limitations of time and place that play so confining
a role in our own time.
The most serious of these limitations emerges from Marx's attempt
to explain the transition from capitalism to socialism, from a class
society to a classless society. It is vitally important to emphasize
that this explanation was reasoned out almost entirely by analogy
with the transition of feudalism to capitalism - that is, from
one class society to another class society, from one system
of property to another. Accordingly, Marx points out that just as
the bourgeoisie developed within feudalism as a result of the split
between town and country (more precisely, between crafts and agriculture),
so the modern proletariat developed within capitalism as a result
of the advance of industrial technology. Both classes, we are told,
develop social interests of their own--indeed, revolutionary social
interests that throw them against the old society in which they
were spawned. If the bourgeoisie gained control over economic life
long before it overthrew feudal society, the proletariat, in turn,
gains its own revolutionary power by the fact that it is "disciplined,
united, organized" by the factory system.[4] In both cases,
the development of the productive forces becomes incompatible with
the traditional system of social relations. "The integument
is burst asunder." The old society is replaced by the new.
The critical question we face is this: can we explain the transition
from a class society to a classless society by means of the same
dialectic that accounts for the transition of one class society
to another? This is not a textbook problem that involves the judging
of logical abstractions but a very real and concrete issue for our
time. There are profound differences between the development of
the bourgeoisie under feudalism and the development of the proletariat
under capitalism which Marx either failed to anticipate or never
faced clearly. The bourgeoisie controlled economic life long before
it took state power; it had become the dominant class materially,
culturally and ideologically before it asserted its dominance politically.
The proletariat does not control economic life. Despite its indispensable
role in the industrial process, the industrial working class is
not even a majority of the population, and its strategic economic
position is being eroded by cybernation and other technological
advances.[5] Hence it requires an act of high consciousness for
the proletariat to use its power to achieve a social revolution.
Until now, the achievement of this consciousness has been blocked
by the fact that the factory milieu is one of the most well entrenched
arenas of the work ethic, of hierarchical systems of management,
of obedience to leaders, and in recent times of production committed
to superfluous commodities and armaments. The factory serves not
only to "discipline," "unite," and "organize"
the workers, but also to do so in a thoroughly bourgeois fashion.
In the factory, capitalistic production not only renews the social
relations of capitalism with each working day, as Marx observed,
it also renews the psyche, values and ideologies of capitalism.
Marx sensed this fact sufficiently to look for reasons more compelling
than the mere fact of exploitation or conflicts over wages and hours
to propel the proletariat into revolutionary action. In his general
theory of capitalist accumulation he tried to delineate the harsh,
objective laws that force the proletariat to assume a revolutionary
role. Accordingly, he developed his famous theory of immiseration:
competition between capitalists compels them to undercut each other's
prices, which in turn leads to a continual reduction of wages and
the absolute impoverishment of the workers. The proletariat is compelled
to revolt because with the process of competition and the centralization
of capital there "grows the mass of misery, oppression, slavery,
degradation."[6]
But capitalism has not stood still since Marx's day. Writing in
the middle years of the nineteenth century, Marx could not be expected
to grasp the full consequences of his insights into the centralization
of capital and the development of technology. He could not be expected
to foresee that capitalism would develop not only from mercantilism
into the dominant industrial form of his day--from state-aided trading
monopolies into highly competitive industrial units--but further,
that with the centralization of capital, capitalism returns to its
mercantilist origins on a higher level of development and reassumes
the state-aided monopolistic form. The economy tends to merge with
the state and capitalism begins to "plan" its development
instead of leaving it exclusively to the interplay of competition
an market forces. To be sure, the system does not abolish the traditional
class struggle, but manages to contain it, using its immense technological
resources to assimilate the most strategic sections of the working
class.
Thus the full thrust of the immiseration theory is blunted and
in the United States the traditional class struggle fails to develop
into the class war. It remains entirely within bourgeois dimensions.
Marxism, in fact, becomes ideology. It is assimilated by the most
advanced forms of state capitalist movement - notably Russia. By
an incredible irony of history, Marxian "socialism" turns
out to be in large part the very state capitalism that Marx failed
to anticipate in the dialectic of capitalism.[7] The proletariat,
instead of developing into a revolutionary class within the womb
of capitalism, turns out to be an organ within the body of bourgeois
society.
The question we must ask at this late date in history is whether
a social revolution that seeks to achieve a classless society can
emerge from a conflict between traditional classes in a class society,
or whether such a social revolution can only emerge from the decomposition
of the traditional classes, indeed from the emergence of an entirely
new "class" whose very essence is that it is a non-class,
a growing stratum called the revolutionary? In trying to
answer this question, we can learn more by returning to the broader
dialectic which Marx developed for human society as a whole than
from the model he borrowed from the passage of feudal into capitalist
society. Just as primitive kinship clans began to differentiate
into classes, so in our own day there is a tendency for
classes to decompose into entirely new subcultures which bear a
resemblance to non-capitalist forms of relationships. These are
not strictly economic groups anymore; in fact, they reflect the
tendency of the social development to transcend the economic categories
of scarcity society. They constitute, in effect, a crude, ambiguous
cultural preformation of the movement of scarcity into post-scarcity
society.
The process of class decomposition must be understood in all its
dimensions. The word "process" must be emphasized here:
the traditional classes do not disappear, nor for that
matter does class struggle. Only a social revolution could remove
the prevailing class structure and the conflict engenders. The point
is the traditional class struggle ceases to have revolutionary implications;
it reveals itself as the physiology of the prevailing society, not
as the labor pains of birth. In fact the traditional class struggle
stabilizes capitalist society by "correcting" its abuses
(in wages, hours, inflation, employment, etc.). The unions in capitalist
society constitute themselves into a counter-"monopoly"
to the industrial monopolies and are incorporated into the neomercantile
statified economy as an estate. Within this estate there are lesser
or greater conflicts, but taken as a whole the unions strengthen
the system and serve to perpetuate it.
To reinforce this class structure by babbling about the "role
of the working class," to reinforce the traditional class struggle
by imputing a "revolutionary" content to it, to infect
the new revolutionary movement of our time with "workeritis"
is reactionary to the core. How often do the Marxian doctrinaires
have to be reminded that the history of the class struggle is the
history of a disease, of the wounds opened by the famous "social
question," of man's one-sided development in trying to gain
control over nature by dominating his fellow man? If the byproduct
of this disease has been technological advance, the main products
have been repression, a horrible shedding of human blood and a terrifying
distortion of the human psyche.
As the disease approaches its end, as the wound begins to heal
in their deepest recesses, the process now unfolds toward wholeness;
the revolutionary implications of the traditional class
struggle lose their meaning as theoretical constructs and as social
reality. The process of decomposition embraces not only the traditional
class structure but also the patriarchal family, authoritarian modes
of upbringing, the influence of religion, the institutions of the
state, and the mores built around toil, renunciation, guilt and
repressed sexuality. The process of disintegration in short,
now becomes generalized and cuts across virtually all the traditional
classes, values and institutions. It creates entirely new issues,
modes of struggle and forms of organization and calls for an entirely
new approach to theory and praxis.
What does this mean concretely? Let us contrast two approaches,
the Marxian and the revolutionary. The Marxian doctrinaire would
have us approach the worker - or better, "enter" the factory
- and proselytize him in "preference" to anyone else.
The purpose? - to make the worker "class conscious." To
cite the most neanderthal examples from the old left, one cuts one's
hair, grooms oneself in conventional sports clothing, abandons pot
for cigarettes and beer, dances conventionally, affects "rough"
mannerisms, and develops a humorless, deadpan and pompous mien.[8]
One becomes, in short, what the worker is at his most caricaturized
worst: not a "petty bourgeois degenerate," to be sure,
but a bourgeois degenerate. One becomes an imitation of
the worker insofar as the worker is an imitation of his masters.
Beneath the metamorphosis of the student into the "worker"
lies a vicious cynicism. One tries to use the discipline inculcated
by the factory milieu to discipline the worker to the party milieu.
One tries to use the worker's respect for the industrial hierarchy
to wed the worker to the party hierarchy. This disgusting process,
which if successful could lead only to the substitution of one hierarchy
for another, is achieved by pretending to be concerned with the
worker's economic day-to-day demands. Even Marxian theory is degraded
to accord with this debased image of the worker. (See almost any
copy of "Challenge" - the "New York Enquirer"
of the "left." Nothing bores the worker more than this
kind of shit literature.) In the end, the worker is shrewd enough
to know what he will get better results in the day-to-day class
struggle through his union bureaucracy than through a Marxian party
bureaucracy. The forties revealed this so dramatically that within
a year or two, , unions succeeded in kicking out "Marxians"
by the thousands (with hardly any protest from the rank-and-file)
who had done spade-work in the labor movement for more than a decade,
even rising to the top leadership of the old C.I.O. internationals.
The worker becomes a revolutionary not by becoming more
of a worker but by undoing his "workerness." And in this
he is not alone; the same applies to the farmer, the student, the
clerk, the soldier, the bureaucrat, the professional - and the Marxist.
The worker is no less a "bourgeois" than the farmer, student,
clerk, soldier, bureaucrat, professional - and Marxist. His "workerness"
is the disease he is suffering from, the social affliction telescoped
to individual dimensions. Lenin understood this in What Is to
Be Done? but he smuggled in the old hierarchy under a red flag
and some revolutionary verbiage. The worker begins to become a revolutionary
when he undoes his "workerness," when he comes to detest
his class status here and now, when he begins to disgorge exactly
those feaures which the Marxists most prize in him: his respect
for hierarchy, his obedience to leaders, his consumerism, his vestiges
of puritanism. in this sense, the worker becomes a revolutionary
to the degree that he sheds his class status and achieves an un-class
consciousness. He degenerates - and he degenerates magnificently.
What he is shedding are precisely those class shackles that bind
him to all systems of domination. He abandons those class interests
that enslave him to consumerism, suburbia, and a bookkeeping conception
of life.[9]
The most promising development in the factories today is the emergence
of young workers who smoke pot, fuck-off on their jobs, drift into
and out of factories, grow long or longish hair, demand more leisure
time rather than more pay, steal, harass all authority figures,
go on wildcats, and turn on their fellow workers. Even more promising
is the emergence of this human type in trade schools and high schools,
the reservoir of the industrial working class to come. To the degree
that workers, vocational students, and high school students link
their life-styles to various aspects of the anarchic youth culture,
to that degree will the proletariat be transformed from a force
for the conservation of the established order into a force for revolution.
A qualitatively new situation emerges when man is faced with a
transformation from a repressive, class society, based on material
scarcity, into a liberatory, classless society, based on material
abundance. From the decomposing traditional class structure, a new
human type is created in ever-increasing numbers: the revolutionary.
This revolutionary begins to challenge not only the economic and
political premises of hierarchical society, but hierarchy as such.
He raises not only the need for social revolution but tries to live
in a revolutionary manner to the degree that this is possible in
the existing society.[10] He attacks not only the forms created
by the legacy of domination, but improvises new forms of liberation
which take their poetry from the future.
This preparation for the future, this experimentation with liberatory,
post-scarcity forms of social relations, may be illusory if the
future involves a substitution of one class society by another;
it is indispensable, however, if the future involves a classless
society built on the ruins of a class society. What, then, will
be the "agent" of revolutionary change? Literally, the
great majority of society, drawn from all the different traditional
classes and funded into a common revolutionary force by the decomposition
of the institutions, social forms, values, and life-styles of the
prevailing class structure. Typically, its most advanced elements
are the youth - a generation, today, that has known no chronic economic
crisis, that is less and less oriented toward the myth of material
security so widespread among the generation of the thirties.
If it is true that a social revolution cannot be achieved without
the active or passive support of the workers, it is no less true
that it cannot be achieved without the active or passive support
of the farmers, technicians, and professionals. Above all, a social
revolution cannot be achieved without the support of the youth,
from which the ruling class recruits its armed forces. If the ruling
class retains its armed might, the revolution is lost no matter
how many workers rally to its support. This has been vividly
demonstrated not only by Spain in the thirties but by Hungary in
the fifties and Czechoslovakia in the sixties. The revolution of
today - by its very nature, indeed, in its pursuit of wholeness
- wins not only the soldier and the worker, but the very generation
from which soldiers, workers, technicians, farmers, scientists,
professionals, and even bureaucrats have been recruited. Discarding
the tactical handbooks of the past, the revolution of the future
follows the path of least resistance, eating its way into the most
susceptible areas of the population, irrespective of their "class
position." It is nourished by all the contradictions in bourgeois
society, not by preconceived ones borrowed from the 1860's and 1917.
Hence it attracts all those who feel the burdens of exploitation,
poverty, racism, imperialism and, yes, those whose lives are frustrated
by consumerism, suburbia, the mass media, the family, school, supermarket,
and the prevailing system of repressed sexuality. Here the form
of the revolution becomes as totalistic as its content: classless,
propertyless, hierarchyless, and wholly liberating.
To barge into this revolutionary development with the worn recipes
of Marxism, to babble about a "class line" and the "role
of the working class," amounts to subverting the present and
future by the past. To elaborate this deadening ideology by babbling
about "cadres," a "vanguard party," "democratic
centralism" and the "proletarian dictatorship" is
sheer counterrevolution. It is this matter of the "organizational
question" - this vital contribution of Leninism to Marxism
- that we must now direct some attention.
The Myth of the Party
Social revolutions are not "made" by "parties,"
groups, or cadres; they occur as a result of deep-seated historic
forces and contradictions that activate large sections of the population.
They occur not merely (as Trotsky argued) because the "masses"
find the existing society intolerable, but also because of the tension
between the actual and the possible, between "what is"
and "what could be." Abject misery alone does
not produce revolutions; more often than not, it produces an aimless
demoralization, or worse, a private, personalized struggle to survive.
The Russian Revolution of 1917 weighs on the brain of the living
like a nightmare because it was largely a product of "intolerable
conditions," of a devastating imperialistic war. Whatever dreams
it had were pulverized by an even bloodier civil war, by famine,
and by treachery. What emerged from the revolution were the ruins
not of an old society but of whatever hopes existed to achieve a
new one. The Russian Revolution failed miserably; it replaced Tsarism
by state capitalism.[11] The Bolsheviks were the tragic victims
of their ideology and paid with their lives in great numbers during
the purges of the thirties. To attempt to acquire any unique wisdom
from this scarcity revolution is ridiculous. What we can learn from
the revolutions of the past is what all revolutions have in common
and their profound limitations compared with the enormous possibilities
that are now open to us.
The most striking feature of the past revolutions is that they
began spontaneously. Whether one chooses to examine the opening
phases of the French Revolution of 1789, the revolutions of 1848,
the Paris Commune, the 1905 revolution in Russia, the overthrow
of the Tsar in 1917, the Hungarian Revolution of 1956, the French
general strike of 1968, the opening stages are generally the same:
a period of ferment that explodes spontaneously into a mass upsurge.
Whether the upsurge is successful or not depends on its resoluteness
and on whether the State can effectively exercise its armed power
- that is, on whether the troops go over to the people.
The "glorious party," when there is one, almost invariably
lags behind the events. In February, 1917, the Petrograd organization
of the Bolsheviks opposed the calling of strikes precisely on the
eve of the revolution which was destined to overthrow the Tsar.
Fortunately, the workers ignored the Bolshevik "directives"
and went on strike anyway. In the events which followed, no one
was more surprised by the revolution than the "revolutionary"
parties, including the Bolsheviks. As the Bolshevik leader Kayurov
recalled: "Absolutely no guiding initiatives from the party
were felt . . . the Petrograd committee had been arrested and the
representative from the Central Committee, Comrade Shliapnikov,
was unable to give any directives for the coming day." Perhaps
this was fortunate: before the Petrograd committee was arrested,
its evaluation of the situation and its role were so dismal that,
had the workers followed its guidance, it is doubtful if the revolution
would have occurred when it did.
The same kind of stories could be told of the upsurges which preceded
1917 and those which followed. To cite only the most recent: the
student uprising and general strike in France during May-June, 1968.
There is a convenient tendency to forget that close to a dozen "tightly
centralized" Bolshevik-type organizations existed in Paris
at this time. It is rarely mentioned that virtually every one of
these "vanguard" groups were disdainful of the student
uprising up to May 7th, when the street fighting broke out in earnest.
The Trotskyist J.C.R. was a notable exception - and it merely coasted
along, essentially following the initiatives of the March 22nd Movement.[12]
Up to May 7th, all the Maoist groups criticized the student uprising
as peripheral and unimportant; the Trotskyist F.E.R. regarded it
as "adventuristic" and tried to get the students to leave
the barricades on May 10th; the Communist Party, of course, played
a completely treacherous role. Far from leading the popular movement,
they were its captives throughout. Ironically, most of these Bolshevik
groups were to manipulate shamelessly in the Sorbonne student assembly
in an effort to "control" it, introducing a disruptive
atmosphere that demoralized the entire body. Finally, to complete
the irony, all of these Bolshevik groups were to babble about the
need for "centralized leadership" when the popular movement
collapsed - a movement that occurred despite their directives and
often in opposition to them.
Revolutions and uprisings worthy of any note not only have an
initial phase that is magnificently anarchic but also tend spontaneously
to create their own forms of revolutionary self-management.
The Parisian sections of 1793-94 were the most remarkable forms
of self-management to be created by any of the social revolutions
in history. [13] A more familiar form were the councils or "soviets,"
which the Petrograd workers established in 1905. Although less democratic
than the sections, the council form was to reappear in a number
of revolutions of later years. Still another form of revolutionary
self-managernent were the factory committees which the anarchists
established in the Spanish Revolution of 1936. Finally, the sections
reappeared as student assemblies and action committees in the Slay-June
uprising and general strike in Paris a year ago.[14]
We must ask, at this point, what role the "revolutionary"
party plays in all of these developments. In the beginning, as we
have seen, it tends to have an inhibitory function, not a "vanguard"
role. Where it exercises influence, it tends to slow down the flow
of events, not "co-ordinate" the revolutionary forces.
This is not accidental. The party is structured along hierarchical
lines that reflect the very society it professes to oppose.
Despite its theoretical pretensions, it is a bourgeois organism,
a miniature State, with an apparatus and a cadre, whose function
is to seize power, not dissolve power. Rooted in the pre-revolutionary
period, it assimilates all the forms, techniques, and mentality
of a bureaucracy. Its membership is schooled in obedience, in the
preconceptions of a rigid dogma, and taught to revere the "leadership."
The party's leadership, in turn, is schooled in habits born of command,
authority, manipulation, and egomania. This situation is worsened
when the party participates in parliamentary elections. Owing to
the exigencies of election campaigns, the party now models itself
completely on existing bourgeois forms and even acquires the paraphernalia
of the electoral party. The situation assumes truly crucial proportions
when the party acquires large presses, costly headquarters, and
a large inventory of centrally controlled periodicals, and develops
a paid "apparatus" - in short, a bureaucracy with vested
material interests.
As the party expands, the distance between the leadership and
the ranks invariably increases. Its leaders not only become "personages,"
but they lose contact with the living situation below. The local
groups, which know their own immediate situation better than any
remote leader, are obliged to subordinate their insights to directives
from above. The leadership, lacking any direct knowledge of local
problems, responds sluggishly and prudently. Although it stakes
out a claim to the "larger view," to greater "theoretical
competence," the competence of the leadership tends to diminish
the higher one ascends the hierarchy of command. The more one approaches
the level where the real decisions are made, the more conservative
is the nature of the decision-making process, the more bureaucratic
and extraneous are the factors which come into play, the more considerations
of prestige and retrenchment supplant creativity, imagination, and
a disinterested dedication to revolutionary goals.
The result is that the party becomes less efficient from
a revolutionary point of view the more it seeks efficiency in hierarchy,
cadres, and centralization. Although everyone marches in step, the
orders are usually wrong, especially when events begin to move rapidly
and take unexpected turns - as they do in all revolutions. The party
is efficient in only one respect: in molding society in its own
hierarchical image if the revolution is successful. It recreates
bureaucracy, centralization, and the State. It fosters the very
social conditions which justify this kind of society. Hence instead
of "withering away," the State controlled by the "glorious
party" preserves the very conditions which "necessitate"
the existence of a State - and a party to "guard it."
On the other hand, this kind of party is extremely vulnerable
in periods of repression. The bourgeoisie has only to grab its leadership
to virtually destroy the entire movement. With its leaders in prison
or in hiding, the party becomes paralyzed; the obedient membership
has no one to obey and tends to flounder. Demoralization sets in
rapidly. The party decomposes not only because of its repressive
atmosphere but also because of its poverty of inner resources.
The foregoing account is not a series of hypothetical inferences;
it is a composite sketch of all the mass Marxian parties of the
past century - the Social Democrats, the Communists, and the Trotskyist
party of Ceylon, the only mass party of its kind. To claim that
these parties ceased to take their Marxian principles seriously
merely conceals another question: why did this happen in the first
place? The fact is that these parties were co-opted into bourgeois
society because they were structured along bourgeois lines. The
germ of treachery existed in them from birth.
The Bolshevik Party was spared this fate between 1904 and 1917
for only one reason: it was an illegal organization during most
of the years leading up to the revolution. The party was continually
being shattered and reconstituted, with the result that until it
took power it never really hardened into a fully centralized, bureaucratic,
hierarchical machine. Moreover, it was riddled by factions. This
intense factional atmosphere persisted throughout 1917 into the
civil war. Nevertheless the Bolshevik leadership was ordinarily
extremely conservative, a trait that Lenin had to fight throughout
1917 - first, in his efforts to reorient the Central Committee against
the Provisional Government (the famous conflict over the "April
Theses"), later in driving this body into insurrection in October.
In both cases, he threatened to resign from the Central Committee
and bring his views to "the lower ranks of the party."
In 1918, factional disputes became so serious over the issue of
the Brest-Litovsk Treaty that the Bolsheviks nearly split into two
warring Communist parties. Oppositional Bolshevik groups like the
Democratic Centralists and the Workers' opposition waged bitter
struggles within the party throughout 1919 and 1920, not to speak
of oppositional movements that developed within the Red Army over
Trotsky's propensity for centralization. The complete centralization
of the Bolshevik Party - the achievement of "Leninist unity,"
as it was to be called later - did not occur until 1921, when Lenin
succeeded in persuading the Tenth Party Congress to ban factions.
By this time, most of the White Guards had been crushed and the
foreign interventionists had withdrawn their troops from Russia.
It cannot be stressed too strongly that the Bolsheviks tended
to centralize their party to the degree that they became isolated
from the working class. This relationship has rarely been investigated
in latter-day Leninist circles, although Lenin was honest enough
to admit it. The Russian Revolution is not merely the story of the
Bolshevik Party and its supporters. Beneath the veneer of official
events described by Soviet historians there was another, more basic
development - the spontaneous movement of the workers and revolutionary
peasants, which later clashed sharply with the bureaucratic policies
of the Bolsheviks. With the overthrow of the Tsar in February, 1917,
workers in virtually all the factories of Russia spontaneously established
factory committees, staking out an increasing claim in industrial
operations. In June, 1917, an all-Russian Conference of Factory
Committees was held in Petrograd which called for the "organization
of thorough control by labor over production and distribution."
The demands of this Conference are rarely mentioned in Leninist
accounts of the Russian Revolution, despite the fact that the Conference
aligned itself with the Bolsheviks. Trotsky, who describes the factory
committees as "the most direct and indubitable representation
of the proletariat in the whole country," deals with them peripherally
in his massive, three-volume history of the revolution. Yet so important
were these spontaneous organisms of self-management that Lenin,
despairing of winning the soviets in the summer of 1917, was prepared
to jettison the slogan "All Power to the Soviets" for
"All Power to the Factory Committees." This demand would
have catapulted the Bolsheviks into a completely anarchosyndicalist
position, although it is doubtful that they would have remained
there very long.
With the October Revolution, all the factory committees seized
control of the plants, ousting the bourgeoisie and completely taking
control of industrial operations. In accepting the concept of workers'
control, Lenin's famous decree of November 14, 1917, merely acknowledged
an accomplished fact; the Bolsheviks dared not oppose the workers
at this early date. But they began to whittle down the power of
the factory committees. In January, 1918, a scant two months after
"decreeing" workers' control, the Bolsheviks shifted the
administration of the factories from the committees to the bureaucratic
trade unions. The story that the Bolsheviks "patiently"
experimented with workers' control, only to find it "inefficient"
and "chaotic," is a myth. Their "patience" did
not last more than a few weeks. Not only did they end direct workers'
control within a matter of weeks after the decree of November 14,
but even union control came to an end shortly after it had been
established. By the spring of 1918, virtually all Russian industry
was placed under bourgeois forms of management. As Lenin put it,
the "revolution demands . . . precisely in the interests of
socialism that the masses unquestionably obey the single will
of the leaders of the labor process." Workers' control
was denounced not only as "inefficient," "chaotic,"
and "impractical," but as "petty bourgeois"!
The Left Communist Osinsky bitterly denounced all of these spurious
claims and warned the party: "Socialism and socialist organization
must be set up by the proletariat itself, or they will not be set
up at all; something else will be set up - state capitalism."
In the "interests of socialism," the Bolshevik Party elbowed
the proletariat out of every domain it had conquered by its own
efforts and initiative. The party did not coordinate the revolution
or even lead it; it dominated it. First, workers' control, later
union control, were replaced by an elaborate hierarchy, as monstrous
as any structure that existed in pre-revolutionary times. As later
years were to demonstrate, Osinsky's prophecy became bitter reality
with a vengeance.
The problem of "who is to prevail" - the Bolsheviks
or the Russian "masses" - was by no means limited to the
factories. The issue reappeared in the countryside as well as the
cities. A sweeping peasant war had buoyed up the movement of the
workers. Contrary to official Leninist accounts, the agrarian upsurge
was by no means limited to a redistribution of the land into private
plots. In the Ukraine, peasants influenced by the anarchist militias
of Nestor Makhno established a multitude of rural communes, guided
by the communist maxim: "From each according to his ability;
to each according to his needs." Elsewhere, in the north and
in Soviet Asia, several thousands of these organisms were established
partly on the initiative of the Left Social Revolutionaries and
in large measure as a result of traditional collectivist impulses
which stemmed from the Russian village, the mir. It matters
little whether these communes were numerous or embraced large numbers
of peasants; the point is that they were authentic popular organisms,
the nuclei of a moral and social spirit that ranged far above the
dehumanizing values of bourgeois society.
The Bolsheviks frowned upon these organisms from the very beginning
and eventually condemned them. To Lenin, the preferred, the more
"socialist" form of agricultural enterprise was represented
by the State Farm: literally, an agricultural factory in which the
State owned the land and farming equipment, appointing managers
who hired peasants on a wage basis. One sees in these attitudes
toward workers' control and agricultural communes the essentially
bourgeois spirit and mentality that permeated the Bolshevik
Party -a spirit and mentality that emanated not only from its theories,
but from its corporate mode of organization. In December, 1918,
Lenin launched an attack against the communes on the pretext that
peasants were being "forced" to enter them. Actually,
little if any coercion was used to organize these communistic forms
of self-management. As Robert G. Wesson, who studied the Soviet
communes in detail, concludes: "Those who went into communes
must have done so largely of their own volition." The communes
were not suppressed but their growth was discouraged until Stalin
merged the entire development in the forced collectivization drives
of the late twenties and early thirties.
By 1920, the Bolsheviks had isolated themselves from the Russian
working class and peasantry. The elimination of workers' control,
the suppression of the Makhnovtsy, the restrictive political atmosphere
in the country, the inflated bureaucracy, the crushing material
poverty inherited from the civil war years - all, taken together,
generated a deep hostility toward Bolshevik rule. With the end of
hostilities, a new movement surged up from the depths of Russian
society for a "Third Revolution" - not a restoration of
the past, but a deep-felt desire to realize the very goals of freedom,
economic as well as political, that had rallied the "masses"
around the Bolshevik program of 1917. The new movement found its
most conscious form in the Petrograd proletariat and the Kronstadt
sailors. It also found expression in the Party: the growth of anti-centralist
and anarchosyndicalist tendencies among the Bolsheviks reached a
point where a bloc of oppositional groups, oriented toward these
issues, gained 124 seats at a Moscow provincial conference as against
154 for supporters of the Central Committee.
On March 2, 1921, the "Red sailors" of Kronstadt rose
in open rebellion, raising the banner of a "Third Revolution
of the toilers." The Kronstadt program centered around demands
for free elections to the soviets, freedom of speech and press for
the anarchists and Left Socialists parties, free trade unions, and
the liberation of all prisoners who belonged to Socialist parties.
The most shameless stories were fabricated by the Bolsheviks to
account for this uprising, which in later years were acknowledged
as brazen lies. The revolt was characterized as a "White Guard
plot," this despite the fact that the great majority of Communist
Party members in Kronstadt joined the sailors - precisely as
Communists - denouncing the party leaders as betrayers of the
October Revolution. As Robert Vincent Daniels observes in his study
of Bolshevik oppositional movements: "Ordinary Communists were
indeed so unreliable . . . that the government did not depend upon
them, either in the assault on Kronstadt itself or in keeping order
in Petrograd, where Kronstadt's hopes for support chiefly rested.
The main body of troops employed were Chekists and officer cadets
from Red Army training schools. The final assault on Kronstadt was
led by the top officialdom of the Communist Party-a large group
of delegates at the Tenth Party Congress was rushed from Moscow
for this purpose." So weak was the regime internally that the
elite had to do its own dirty work.
Even more significant than the Kronstadt revolt was the strike
movement that developed among the Petrograd workers, a movement
that sparked the uprising of the sailors. Leninist histories do
not recount this critically important development. The first strikes
broke out in the Troubotchny factory on February 23, 1921. Within
a matter of days, the movement swept in one factory after another
until, by February 28, the famous Putilov works - the "crucible
of the Revolution" - went on strike. Not only were economic
demands raised but workers raised distinctly political ones, anticipating
all the demands that were to be raised by the Kronstadt sailors
a few days later. On February 24, the Bolsheviks declared a "state
of siege" in Petrograd and arrested the strike leaders, suppressing
the workers' demonstrations with officer cadets. The fact is that
the Bolsheviks did not merely suppress a "sailors' mutiny";
they crushed by armed force the working class itself. It was at
this point that Lenin demanded the banning of factions in the Russian
Communist Party. Centralization of the party was now complete -
and the way was paved for Stalin.
We have discussed these events in detail because they lead to
a conclusion that our latest crop of Marxist-Leninists tend to avoid:
the Bolshevik Party reached its maximum degree of centralization
in Lenin's day not to achieve a revolution or suppress a White Guard
counterrevolution, but to effect a counterrevolution of its own
against' the very social forces it professed to represent. Factions
were prohibited and a monolithic party created not to prevent a
"capitalist restoration" but to contain a mass movement
of workers for soviet democracy and social freedom. The Lenin of
1921 stood opposed to the Lenin of October, 1917.
Thereafter, Lenin simply floundered. This man, who above all others
sought to anchor the problems of his party in social contradictions,
found himself literally playing an organizational "numbers
game" in a last-ditch attempt to arrest the very bureaucratization
he had himself created. There is nothing more pathetic and tragic
than Lenin's last years. Paralyzed by a simplistic body of Marxist
formulas, he can think of no better countermeasures than organizational
ones. He proposes the formation of the Workers' and Peasants' Inspection
to correct bureaucratic deformations in the Party and State - which
body falls under Stalin's control and becomes highly bureaucratic
in its own right. Lenin then suggests that the size of the Workers'
and Peasants' Inspection be reduced and that it be merged with the
Control Commission. He advocates enlarging the Central Committee.
Thus it rolls along: this body to be enlarged, that one to be merged
with another, still a third to be modified or abolished. The strange
ballet of organizational forms continues up to his very death, as
though the problem could be resolved by organizational means. As
Mosche Lewin, an obvious admirer of Lenin, admits: the Bolshevik
leader "approached the problems of government more like a chief
executive of a strictly `elitist' turn of mind. He did not apply
methods of social analysis to the government and was content to
consider it purely in terms of organizational methods."
If it is true that in the bourgeois revolutions that "phrase
went beyond the content," in the Bolshevik revolution the forms
replaced the content. The soviets replaced the workers and their
factory committees, the Party replaced the soviets, the Central
Committee replaced the Party, and the Political Bureau replaced
the Central Committee. In short, means replaced ends. This incredible
substitution of form for content is one of the most characteristic
traits of Marxism-Leninism. In France, during the May-June events,
all the Bolshevik organizations were prepared to destroy the Sorbonne
student assembly in order to increase their influence and membership.
Their principal concern was not for the revolution or the authentic
social forms created by the students, but the growth of their own
parties. In the United States, an identical situation exists in
P.L.'s relationship with S.D.S.
Only one force could have arrested the growth of bureaucracy in
Russia: a social force. Had the Russian proletariat and peasantry
succeeded in increasing the domain of self-management through the
development of viable factory committees, rural communes, and free
soviets, the history of the country might have taken a dramatically
different turn. There can be no question that the failure of socialist
revolutions in Europe after the First World War led to the isolation
of the revolution in Russia. The material poverty of Russia, coupled
with the pressure of the surrounding capitalist world, clearly militated
against the development of a consistently libertarian, indeed, a
socialist society. But by no means was it ordained that Russia had
to develop along state capitalist lines; contrary to Lenin's and
Trotsky's expectations, the revolution was defeated by internal
forces, not by the invasion of armies from abroad. Had the movement
from below restored the initial achievements of the revolution in
1917, a multi-faceted social structure might have developed, based
on workers' control of industry, on a freely developing peasant
economy in agriculture, and on a living interplay of ideas, programs,
and political movements. At the very least, Russia would have not
been imprisoned in totalitarian chains and Stalinism would not have
poisoned the world revolutionary movement, paving the way for fascism
and World War II.
The development of the Bolshevik Party, however, precluded this
development, Lenin's or Trotsky's "good intentions" aside.
By destroying the power of the factory committees in industry and
by crushing the Makhnovtsy, the Petrograd workers, and the Kronstadt
sailors, the Bolsheviks virtually guaranteed the triumph of the
Russian bureaucracy over Russian society. The centralized party
- a completely bourgeois institution - became the refuge of counterrevolution
in its most sinister form. This was the covert counterrevolution
that draped itself in the red flag and the terminology of Marx.
Ultimately, what the Bolsheviks suppressed in 1921 was not an "ideology"
or a "White Guard conspiracy," but an elemental struggle
of the Russian people to free themselves of their shackles and take
control of their own destiny. For Russia, this meant the nightmare
of Stalinist dictator-ship; for the generation of the thirties it
meant the horror of fascism and the treachery of the Communist parties
in Europe and the United States.
The Two Traditions
It would be incredibly naive to suppose that Leninism
was the aberrant product of a single man. The disease lies much
deeper, not only in the limitations of Marxian theory but in the
limitations of the social era that produced Marxism. If this is
not clearly understood, we will remain as blind to the dialectic
of events today as Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Trotsky were in their
own day. For us, this blindness will be all the more reprehensible
because behind us lies a wealth of experience that these men sorely
lacked in developing their theories.
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels were centralists -
not only politically, but socially and economically. They never
denied this fact and their writings are studded with gleaming encomiums
to political, organizational, and economic centralization. As early
as March, 1850, in the famous Address of the Central Council to
the Communist League, they call upon the workers to strive not only
for "the single and indivisible German republic, but also strive
in it for the most decisive centralization of power in the hands
of the state authority." Lest the demand be taken lightly,
it is repeated continually in the same paragraph, which concludes:
"As in France in 1793, so today in Germany the carrying through
of the strictest centralization is the task of the really revolutionary
party."
The theme reappears continually in later years. With
the outbreak of the Franco-Prussian War, for example, Marx writes
to Engels: "The French need a thrashing. If the Prussians win,
the centralization of state power is useful to the centralization
of the German working class."
Marx and Engels were not centralists, however, because
they believed in the virtues of centralism per se. Quite to the
contrary: both Marxism and anarchism have always agreed that a liberated,
communist society entails sweeping decentralization, the dissolution
of bureaucracy, the abolition of the State, and the break-up of
the large cities. "Abolition of the antithesis between town
and country is not merely possible," notes Engels in Anti-Duhring.
"It has become a direct necessity . . . the present poisoning
of the air, water and land can be put to an end only by the fusion
of town and country. . . ." To Engels, this involves "As
uniform a distribution of the population over the whole country"
- in short, the physical decentralization of the cities.
The origins of Marxian centralism emerge from problems
around the formation of the national state. Until well
into the latter half of the 19th century, Germany and Italy were
divided into a multitude of independent duchies, principalities,
and kingdoms. The consolidation of these geographic units into unified
nations, Marx and Engels believed, was a sine qua non for
the development of modern industry and capitalism. Their praise
of centralism is engendered not by any centralistic mystique but
by the problems of the period in which they lived: the development
of technology, trade, a unified working class and the national state.
Their concern on this score, in short, is with the emergence of
capitalism, with the tasks of the bourgeois revolution in an era
of unavoidable material scarcity. Marx's approach to a "proletarian
revolution," on the other hand, is markedly different. -He
enthusiastically praises the Paris Commune as a "model to all
the
industrial centers of France. This regime," he writes, "once
established in Paris and the secondary centers, the old centralized
government would in the provinces, too, have to give way to the
self-government of the producers." [Our emphasis.]
The unity of the nation, to be sure, would not disappear and a central
government would exist during the transition to communism, but its
functions would be limited.
Our object is not to bandy about quotations from
Marx and Engels, but to emphasize how key tenets of Marxism-which
are accepted so uncritically today-were in fact the product of a
time that has long been transcended by the development of capitalism
in the United States and western Europe. In his day, Marx was occupied
not only with the problems of the "proletarian revolution"
but also with the problems of the bourgeois revolution, particularly
in Germany, Spain, Italy, and eastern Europe. He dealt not only
with problems of transition from capitalism to socialism in capitalist
countries which had not advanced much beyond the coal-steel technology
of the Industrial Revolution; he was also concerned with the problems
of transition from feudalism to capitalism in countries which had
scarcely advanced much beyond handicrafts and the guild system.
To state these concerns more broadly: Marx was occupied above all
with the preconditions of freedom (technological development, national
unification, material abundance) rather than the conditions of freedom
(decentralization, the formation of communities, the human scale,
direct democracy). His theories were still anchored in the realm
of survival, not the realm of life.
Once this is grasped it is possible to place Marx's
theoretical legacy in meaningful perspective - to separate its rich
contributions from its historically limited, indeed, paralyzing
shackles on our own time. The Marxian dialectic, the many seminal
insights provided by histor-ical materialism, the superb critique
of the commodity relationship, many elements of the economic theories,
the theory of alienation, and above all, the notion that freedom
has material preconditions-these are lasting contributions to revolutionary
thought.
By the same token, Marx's emphasis on the industrial
proletariat as the "agent" of revolutionary change, his
"class analysis" in explaining the transition from a class
to a classless society, his concept of the pro-letarian dictatorship,
his emphasis on centralism, his theory of the capitalist development
which tends to jumble state capitalism with socialism, his advocacy
of political action through electoral parties-these and many related
concepts are false in the context of our time and were misleading,
as we shall see, even in his own day. They emerge from the limitations
of his vision, more properly, from the limitations of his time.
They make sense only if one remembers that Marx regarded capitalism
as historically progressive, as an indispen-sable stage to the development
of socialism, and they have practical applicability only to a time
when Germany in particular was con-fronted by bourgeois-democratic
tasks and national unification. In taking this retrospective approach,
we are not trying to say that Marx was correct in holding this approach
- merely, that the approach makes sense when viewed in its time
and place.
Just as the Russian Revolution included a subterranean
movement of the "masses" which conflicted with Bolshevism,
so there is a sub-terranean movement in history which has conflicted
with all systems of authority. This movement has entered into our
time under the name of "anarchism," although it has never
been encompassed by a single ideology or body of sacred texts. Anarchism
is a libidinal movement of humanity against coercion in any form,
reaching back in time to the very emergence of propertied society,
class rule, and the State. From this period onward, the oppressed
have resisted all forms that seek to imprison the spontaneous development
of social order. By whatever name men chose to call it, anarchism
surged to the foreground of the social arena in periods of major
transition from one historical era to another. The decline of the
ancient and feudal world witnessed the upsurge of mass movements,
in some cases, wildly Dionysian in character, that demanded an end
to all systems of author-ity, privilege, and coercion.
The anarchic movements of the past failed largely
because material scarcity, a function of the low level of technology,
vitiated an organic harmonization of human interests. Any society
that could promise little more materially than equality of poverty
invariably engendered deep-seated tendencies to restore a new system
of privilege. In the absence of a technology that could appreciably
reduce the working day, the need to work vitiated social institutions
based on self-management. The Girondins of the French Revolution
shrewdly recognized that they could use the working day against
revolutionary Paris. To exclude radical elements from the sections,
they tried to enact legislation which would end all assembly meetings
before 9 P.M., the hour when Parisian workers returned from their
jobs. Indeed, it was not only the manipulative techniques and the
treachery of the "vanguard" organizations that brought
the anarchic phase of past revolutions to an end; it was also the
material limits of past eras. The "masses" were always
compelled to return to a lifetime of toil and rarely were they free
to establish organs of self-management that could last beyond the
revolution.
Anarchists such as Bakunin and Kropotkin, however,
were by no means wrong in criticizing Marx for his emphasis on centralism
and his elitist notions of organization. Was centralism absolutely
necessary for technological advances in the past? Was the nation-state
indispensable to the expansion of commerce? Did the workers' movement
benefit by the emergence of highly centralized economic enterprises
and the "indivisible" State? We tend to accept these tenets
of Marxism too uncritically, largely because capitalism developed
within a centralized political arena. The anarchists of the last
century warned that Marx's centralistic approach, insofar as it
affected the events of the time, would so strengthen the bourgeoisie
and the State apparatus that this development would make the overthrow
of capitalism extremely difficult. The revolutionary party, by duplicating
these centralistic, hierarchical features, would reproduce hierarchy
and centralism in the post-revolutionary society.
Bakunin, Kropotkin, and Malatesta were not so naive
as to believe that anarchy could be established overnight. In imputing
this notion to Bakunin, Marx and Engels willfully distorted the
Russian anarchist's views. Nor did the anarchists of the last century
believe that the abolition of the State involved "laying down
arms" immediately after the revolution, to use Marx's obscurantist
choice of terms, and which Lenin thoughtlessly repeated in State
and Revolution. Indeed, much that passes for "Marxism"
in State and Revolution is pure anarchism: the substitution
of revolutionary militias for professional armed bodies, the substitution
of organs of self-management for parliamentary bodies. What is authentically
Marxist in Lenin's pamphlet is the demand for "strict centralism,"
the acceptance of a "new" bureaucracy, the identification
of soviets with a State.
The anarchists of the last century were deeply preoccupied
with the question of achieving industrialization without crushing
the revolutionary spirit of the "masses" and rearing new
obstacles to emancipation. They feared that centralization would
reinforce the ability of the bourgeoisie to resist the revolution
and instill in the workers a sense of obedience. They tried to rescue
all those pre-capitalist communal forms (such as the Russian mir
and the Spanish pueblo) which might provide a springboard
to a free society, not only in a structural sense but also a spiritual
one.
Hence they emphasized the need for decentralization
even under capitalism. In contrast to the Marxian parties, their
organizations gave considerable attention to what they called "integral
education" - the development of the whole man - to counteract
the debasing and banalizing influence of bourgeois society. The
anarchists tried to live by the values of the future to the extent
that this was possible under capitalism. They believed in direct
action in order to foster the initiative of the "masses,"
to preserve the spirit of revolt, to encourage spontaneity. They
tried to develop organizations based on mutual aid and brotherhood,
in which control would be exercised from below upward, not from
above downward.
We must pause, here, to examine the nature of anarchist
organizational forms in some detail if only because the subject
has been obscured by an appalling amount of rubbish. Anarchists,
or at least anarchist communists, accept the need for organization.[15]
It should be as absurd to have to repeat this point as to argue
over whether Marx accepted the need for social revolution.
The real question at issue here is not organization
versus non-organization, but rather, what kind of organization the
anarchist communists try to establish. What the different kinds
of anarchist communist organizations have in common is that they
are developed organically from below, not engineered into existence
from above. They are social movements, combining a creative revolutionary
lifestyle with a creative revolutionary theory, not political parties,
whose mode of life is indistinguishable from the surrounding bourgeois
environment and whose ideology is reduced to rigid "tried and
tested programs." They try to reflect as much as is humanly
possible the liberated society they seek to achieve, not slavishly
duplicate the prevailing system of hierarchy, class and authority.
They are built around intimate groups of brothers and sisters -
affinity groups - whose ability to act in common is based on initiative,
on convictions freely arrived at and a deep personal involvement,
not a bureaucratic apparatus fleshed out by a docile membership
and manipulated from above by a handful of all-knowing leaders.
The anarchist communists do not deny the need for
coordination between groups, for discipline, for meticulous planning,
and unity in action. But they believe that coordination, discipline,
planning and unity in action must be achieved voluntarily, by means
of a self-discipline nourished by conviction and understanding,
not by coercion and a mindless, unquestioning obedience to orders
from above. They seek to achieve the effectiveness imputed to centralism
by means of voluntarism and insight, not by establishing a hierarchical,
centralized structure. Depending upon needs or circumstances, affinity
groups can achieve this effectiveness through assemblies, action
committees, and local, regional or national conferences. But they
vigorously oppose the establishment of an organizational structure
that becomes an end in itself, of committees that linger on after
their practical tasks have been completed, of a "leadership"
that reduces the "revolutionary" to a mindless robot.
These conclusions are not the result of flighty "individualistic"
impulses; quite to the contrary, they emerge from an exacting study
of past revolutions, of the impact centralized parties have had
on the revolutionary process and the nature of social change in
an era of potential material abundance. Anarchist communists seek
to preserve and extend the anarchic phase that opens all the great
social revolutions. Even more than Marxists, they recognize
that revolutions are produced by deep historical processes. No Central
Committee "makes" a social revolution; at best it can
stage a coup d'etat, replacing one hierarchy by another
- or worse, arrest a revolutionary process if it exercises any widespread
influence. A Central Committee is an organ for acquiring power,
for recreating power, for gathering to itself what the "masses"
have achieved by their own revolutionary efforts. One must be blind
to all that has happened over the past two centuries not to recognize
these essential facts.
In the past, Marxists could make an intelligible,
although not a valid, claim for the need for a centralized party,
because the anarchic phase of the revolution was vitiated by material
scarcity. Economically, the "masses" were always compelled
to return to a daily life of toil. The revolution closed at "nine
o'clock" quite aside from the reactionary intentions of the
Girondins of 1793; it was arrested by the low level of technology.
Today, even this excuse has been removed by the development of a
post-scarcity technology notably in the U.S. and western Europe.
A point has now been reached where the masses can begin, almost
overnight, to expand drastically the "realm of freedom"
in the Marxian sense - to acquire the leisure time needed to achieve
the highest degree of self-management.
What the May-June events in France demonstrated was
not the need for a centralized, Bolshevik-type party (these parties
exist in profusion and they lagged behind the event) but the need
for greater consciousness among the "masses."
Paris demonstrated that an organization is needed to systematically
propagate ideas - and not ideas alone, but ideals which
promote the concept of self-management. What the French
"masses" lacked was not a Central Committee or a Lenin
to "organize" or "command" them, but the conviction
that they could have operated the factories instead of merely occupying
them. It is noteworthy that not a single Bolshevik-type party
in France raised the demand of self-management; the demand
was raised only by the anarchists and the Situationists.
There is a need for a revolutionary organization
- but its function must always be kept clearly in mind. Its first
task is propaganda, to "patiently explain" as Lenin put
it. In a revolutionary situation, the revolutionary organization
presents the most advanced demands: it is prepared at every turn
of events to formulate - in the most concrete fashion - the immediate
task that should be performed to advance the revolutionary process.
It provides the boldest elements in action and in the decision-making
organs of the revolution.
In what way then, do anarchist communist groups differ
from the Bolshevik-type party? Certainly not on such issues as the
need for organization, planning, coordination, propaganda in all
its forms or the need for a social program. Fundamentally, they
differ from the Bolshevik-type party in their belief that genuine
revolutionaries must function within the framework of the forms
created by the revolution, not within the forms created by
the party. What this means is that their commitment is to the revolutionary
organs of self-management, not the revolutionary "organization";
to the social forms, not the political forms. Anarchist
communists seek to persuade the factory committees, assemblies,
or soviets, to make themselves into genuine organs of popular
self-management, not dominate them, manipulate them, and hitch
them to an all-knowing political party. Anarchist communists do
not seek to rear a state structure over these popular revolutionary
organs but, on the contrary, to dissolve all the organizational
forms developed in the pre-revolutionary period (including their
own) into these genuine revolutionary organs.
These differences with the Bolshevik-type parties
are decisive. Despite their rhetoric and slogans, the Russian Bolsheviks
never believed in the soviets; they regarded them as instruments
of the Bolshevik Party, an attitude which the French Trotskyists
faithfully duplicated in their relations with the Sorbonne students'
assembly, the French Maoists with the C.G.T., and P.L. with S.D.S.
By 1921, the soviets were virtually dead and all decisions were
made by the Bolshevik Central Committee and Political Bureau. Not
only do anarchist communists seek to prevent Marxist parties from
repeating this again; they also wish to prevent their own organization
from playing a similar role. Accordingly, they have tried to prevent
bureaucracy, hierarchy, and elites from emerging in their midst.
No less important, they attempt to remake themselves; to
root out from their own personalities those authoritarian traits
and elitist propensities that are assimilated in propertied society
almost from birth. The concern of the anarchist movement with lifestyle
is not merely a preoccupation with its own integrity, but with the
integrity of the revolution itself.[16]
In the midst of all the confusing ideological cross-currents
of our time, one question must always remain in the foreground:
what the hell are we trying to make a revolution for? Are we trying
to make a revolution to recreate hierarchy again, dangling a shadowy
dream of future freedom before the eyes of humanity? Is it to promote
further technological advance, to create an even greater abundance
of goods than exists today? Is it to "get even" with the
bourgeoisie? Is it to bring P.L. to power? Or the Communist Party?
Or the Socialist Workers Party? Is it to emancipate abstractions
such as "The Pro-letariat," "The People," "History,"
"Society"?
Or is it to finally dissolve hierarchy, class rule,
coercion - to make it possible for each individual to gain control
of his everyday life? Is it to make each moment as marvelous
as it could be and the life span of each individual an utterly fulfilling
experience? If the true purpose of revolution is to bring the Neanderthal
men of P.L. to power, it is not worth making. We need hardly argue
the inane questions of whether individual development can be severed
from social and communal development; obviously the two go together.
The basis for the whole man is a rounded society; the basis for
the free man is the free society.
These issues aside, however, we are still faced with
the question that Marx raised in 1850: when will we begin to take
our poetry from the future instead of the past? The dead must be
permitted to bury the dead. Marxism is dead because it was rooted
in an era of material scarcity, limited in its possibilities by
material want. The most important social message of Marxism is that
freedom has material preconditions; we must survive in order to
live. With the development of a technology that could not have been
conceived by the wildest science-fiction of Marx's day, the possibilities
of a post-scarcity society now lie before us. All the institutions
of propertied society-class rule, hierarchy, the patriarchal family,
bureaucracy, the city, the state-have been exhausted. Today, decentralization
is not only desirable as a means of restoring the human scale; it
becomes necessary to recreate a viable ecology, to preserve life
on this planet from destructive pollutants, soil erosion, the perpetuation
of a breathable atmosphere, the balance of nature. The promotion
of spontaneity is necessary if the social revolution is to place
each individual in control of his everyday life.
The old forms of struggle do not totally disappear
but they are being transcended in the decomposition of class society
by the issues of a classless society. There can be no social revolution
without winning the workers; hence, they must have our active solidarity
in every struggle they wage against exploitation. We fight against
social crimes wherever they appear-and industrial exploitation is
a profound social crime.
But so are racism, the denial of a people's right
to self-determination, imperialism, and poverty profound social
crimes - and for that matter pollution, rampant urbanization, the
malignant socialization of the young, and sexual repression. We
do not make "alliances"; to the contrary, we try to destroy
the very barriers - be they class, cultural, institutional, or psychological
- that make alliances a necessity. The preconditions for the existence
of the bourgeoisie is the development of the proletariat. Capitalism
as a social system presupposes the existence of both classes
and is perpetuated by the development of both classes. We begin
to undermine the premises of class rule to the degree that we foster
the declassifying of the non-bourgeois classes. at least institutionally,
psychologically, and culturally.
For the first time in history, the anarchic phase
that opened all the great revolutions of the past can be preserved
as a permanent condition by the advanced technology of our time.
The anarchic institutions of that phase - the assemblies, the factory
committees, the action committees - can be stabilized as the elements
of a liberated society, as the elements of a new system of self-management.
Will we build a move-ment that can defend them? Can we create an
organization of affinity groups that is capable of dissolving into
these revolutionary institu-tions? Or will we build a hierarchical,
centralized, bureaucratic party that will try to dominate them,
supplant them and finally destroy them?
Listen, Marxist: the organization we try to build
is the kind of society our revolution will create. Either we will
shed the past - in ourselves, as well as in our groups - or there
will simply be no future to win.
Notes
[1] Marxism is above all a theory of
praxis, or to place this relationship in its corrext perspective,
a praxis of theory. This is the very meaning of Marx's transformation
of dialectics from the subjective dimension (to which the Young
Hegelians still tried to confine Hegel's outlook) into the objective,
from philosophical critique into social action. If theory and praxis
become divorced, Marxism is not killed; it commits suicide. This
is its morst admirable and noble feature. The attempts of the cretins
who follow in Marx's wake to keep the system alive with a patchwork
of emendation, exegesis, and above all, a half-ass "scholarship"
a la Maurice Dobb and George Novack, are degrading insults
to Marx's name and a disgusting pollution of everything he stood
for.
[2] It is fascinating to not that Marxists do very
little talking abot the chronic [economic] crisis of capitalism
these days - despite the fact that this concept forms the focal
point of Marx's economic theories.
[3] For ecological reasons, we do not
accept the notion of the "domination of nature by man"
in the simplistic sense that it was passed on by Marx a century
ago. For a discussion of this problem, see this writer's Ecology
and Revolutionary Thought, (Times Change Press).
[4] It is ironical that all the Marixsts
who talk about the "economic power" of the proletariat
are actually echoing the position of the anarchosyndicalists, a
position that Marx bitterly opposed. Marx was not concerned with
the "economic power" of the proletariat but with its political
power: notably, the fact that it would become the majority
of the population. He was convinced that the industrial workers
would be driven to revolution primarily by material destitution
which would follow from the tendency of capitalist accumulation;
that, organized by the factory system and disciplined by
the industrial routing, they would be able to constitute trade unions
and, above all, political parties, which in some countries would
be obliged to use insurrectionary methods and in others (notably,
England, the United States, and in later years Engels added France)
might well come to power in elections and legislate socialism into
existence. Characteristically, many Marxists have been as dishonest
with their Marx and Engels as P.L. has been with the readers of
"Challenge," leaving important observations untranslated
or grossly distorting the meaning and reasons why Marx developed
conclusions of this kind.
[5] This is as good a place as any
to dispose of the notion that a "proletarian" is reducible
to anyone who has nothing to sell but his labor power. It is true
that Marx defined the proletariat in these terms but he alse worked
out a historical dialectic in the development of the proletariat.
The proletariat developed out of a propertyless, exploited class,
reaching its most "mature" form in the industrial
proletariat. This class, according to Marx, was the
most advanced form, corresponding to the most advance form of capital.
In the late years of his life, Marx came to despise the Parisian
workers, who were engaged preponderantly in the production of luxury
goods, citing "our German workers" - the most robot-like
in Europe - as the "model" proletariat of the world.
[6]The attempt to describe Marx's immiseration
theory in international terms instead of national (as Marx did)
is sheer subterfuge. In the first place, this theoretical legerdemain
simply tries to sidestep the reasons why immiseration has not occured
within the industrial strongholds of capitalism, the only areas
which form a technologically adequate point of departure for a classless
society. If we are to pin our hopes on the colonial world as
"the proletariat," this position conceals a very real
danger: genocide. America and her recent ally, Russia, have all
the technical means to bomb the underdeveloped world into submission.
This threat lurks on the hisorical horizon - the development of
the United Staes into a truly fascist imperium of the Nazi type.
It is sheer rubbish to say that this county is a "paper tiger."
It is a termonuclear tiger and the American ruling class, owing
to the absence of any cultural restraints, is capable of being even
more vicious than the German.
[7] Lenin sensed this and described
"socialism" as "nothing but state capitalist monopoly
made to benefit the whole people." This is an extraordinary
statement if one thinks out its implications, and a mouthful of
contradictions.
[8]On this score, the Old Left projects
its own neanderthal image on the American worker. Actually this
image more closely approximates the character of the union bureaucrat
or the Stalinist commissar.
[9] The worker, in this sense, begins
to approximate the socially transitional human types who provided
history with its most revolutionary elements. Generally, the "proletariat"
has been most revolutionary in transitional periods, when it was
least "proletarianized" psychically by the industrial
system. The great foci of the classical workers' revolutions were
Petrograd and Barcelona, where the workers had been directly uprooted
from a peasant background, and Paris, where they were still anchored
in crafts or came directly from a craft background. These workers
had the greatest difficulty in acclimating themselves to industrial
domination and became a continual source of social and revolutionary
unrest.
By contrast, the stable, hereditary working class tended to be surprisingly
non-revolutionary. Even in the much-cited case of the German workers
(which, as we know, had been cited by Marx and Engels as models
for the European proletariat), the majority did not support the
Spartacists in 1919. They returned large majorities of official
Social Democrats to the Congress of Workers' Councils, to the Reichstag
in later years, and rallied consistently behind the Social Democratic
Party right up to 1933.
[10] This revolutionary life-style
may develop in the factories as well as on the streets, in schools
as well as in crashpads, in the suburbs as well as the Bay Area-East
Side axis. Its essence is defiance, and a personal "propaganda
of the deed" that erodes all the mores, institutions, and shibboleths
of domination.
As society begins to approach the threshold of the revolutionary
period, the factories, schools, and neighborhoods become the actual
arena of revolutionary "play" - a "play" that
has a very serious core. Strikes become a chronic condition and
are called for their own sake, to break the veneer of routine, to
defy the society on an almost hourly basis, to shatter the mood
of bourgeois normality. This new mood of the workers, students,
and neighborhood people is a vital precursor to the actual moment
of revolutionary transformation. Its most conscious expression is
the demand for "self-management"; the worker refuses to
be a "managed" being, a class being. This is an eminently
revolutionary demand even if it takes its point of departure from
the factory, the economic arena of the arena of survival.
This process was most evident, historically, in the Paris Commune
and especially in Spain, on the eve of the 1936 revolution, when
workers in almost every city and town called strikes "for the
hell of it"- to express their independence, their sense of
awakening, their break with the social order and with bourgeois
conditions of life. This was also an essential feature of the 1968
general strike in France.
[11] A fact which Trotsky never understood.
He never followed through the consequences of his own concept of
"combined development" to its logical conclusions. He
saw (quite correctly) that Tsarist Russia, the late-comer in the
European bourgeois development, necessarily acquired the most advanced
industrial and class forms instead of recapitulating the entire
bourgeois de-velopment from its beginnings. He neglected to consider
that Russia, torn by a tremendous internal upheaval, might even
run ahead of the capitalist development elsewhere in Europe. Hypnotized
by the formula, "nationalized property = socialism," he
failed to recognize that monopoly capitalism itself tends to
amalgamate with the State by its own inner dialectic.
The Bolsheviks, having cleared away the traditional forms of bourgeois
social organization (which still act as a rein on the state capitalist
development in Europe and America), inadvertently prepared the ground
for a "pure" state capitalist development in which the
State finally becomes the ruling class. Lacking support from a technologically
advanced Europe, the Russian Revolution passed into an internal
counterrevolution; Soviet Russia became a form of state capitalism
that does not "benefit the whole people." Lenin's analogy
between "socialism" and state capitalism became a terrifying
reality under Stalin.
Despite its humanistic core, Marxism failed to comprehend how much
its concept of "socialism" approximates a later stage
of capitalism itself: the return to neo-mercantilist forms on a
higher industrial level. To fail to understand this development
is to create devastating theoretical confusion in the contemporary
revolutionary movement, as witness the splits within the Trotskyist
movement over this question.
[12] The March
22nd Movement functioned as a catalytic agent in the events, not
as a leadership. It did not "command"; it instigated,
leaving a free play to the events. This free play which allowed
the students to push ahead on their own momentum was indispensable
to the dialectic of the uprising, for without it there would have
been no barricades on May 10th, which in turn triggered off the
general strike of the workers.
[13] It is unfortunate that so little
has been written about the Parisian sections in English. The sections
were neighborhood associations based on face-to-face democracy,
not on representation. These extraordinary bodies not only provided
the real momentum of the Great French Revolution but they undertook
the administration of the entire city. They policed their own neighborhoods,
elected their own revolutionary tribunals, were responsible for
the distribution of foodstuffs, provided public aid for the poor.
and contributed to the maintenance of the National Guard. It must
be borne in mind that this complex of extremely important activities
was undertaken not by professional bureaucrats, but for the most
part by ordinary shopkeepers, workers and craftsmen. The bulk of
sectional responsibilities were discharged after working hours,
during the leisure time of the section members. The popular assemblies
of the sections usually met during the evenings in neighborhood
churches which had been expropriated for their use and were open
to all citizens, without property qualifications after the summer
of 1792. In periods of emergency, assembly meetings were held daily;
normally, they could be called at the request of fifty members.
Most administrative responsibilities were discharged by committees,
but the popular assemblies established all the policies of the committees,
reviewed and passed on their work, and replaced section officers
at will. It is not too difficult to surmise why these sections have
received very little attention by Marxist theoreticians: they were
much too "anarchic" to please the pontiffs of the "Left."
[14] With a sublime arrogance that
is accountable partly to ignorance, a number of Marxist groups were
to dub virtually all of the above forms of self-management as "soviets."
The attempt to bring all of these different forms under a single
rubric is not only misleading but willfully obscurantist. The actual
soviets were the least democratic of the revolutionary forms and
the Bolsheviks shrewdly used them to transfer the power to their
own party. The soviets were not based on face-to-face democracy,
like the Parisian sections or like the Parisian student assemblies
of 1968. Nor were they based on economic self-management, like the
Spanish anarchist factory committees. The soviets were actually
a workers parliament, hierarchically organized. which drew their
representation from factories, later military units and peasant
villages. Despite its "class character,' the Congress of Soviets
was a geographic organism which structurally differed little from
the House of Representatives and soon surrendered its power to an
executive, staffed by the Bolshevik Party. In short, the soviets
were a State which existed over the working class, not of
it.
[15] The term "anarchist"
is a generic word, like the term "socialist" and there
are probably as many different kinds of anarchists as there are
socialists. In both cases, the spectrum ranges from individuals
whose views derive from an extension of liberalism (the "individualist
anarchists," the Social Democrats) to revolutionary communists
(the anarchist communists, the revolutionary Marxists, Leninists,
and Trotskyists).
[16] It is this
goal, we may add, that motivates anarchist Dadaism-the "an-archist
flipout"-that produces the creases of consternation on the
wooden faces of P.L. types. The "anarchist flipout" attempts
to shatter the internal values inherited from hierarchical society,
to explode the rigidities instilled by the bourgeois socialization
process ; indeed to restore a sense of desire, possibility, the
marvels of revolution as a liberating joyous festival.
Subject Headings
|
Connect with Connexions
Newsletter Facebook Twitter
|