www.newsandletters.org












NEWS & LETTERS, October 2002

PHILOSOPHIC DIALOGUE

The theory and politics of regression

by Tom More

In the worlds colliding today, to which the Bush administration's answer is the drive towards permanent war, the thought is in motion of a new crusade, a "holy cause." The President's rhetoric of a nearly cosmic clash between the forces of light and darkness, his projection of an "axis of evil," discloses the essentially religious character of his own idea of history, evident from his "born again" Christianity.

Islamic fundamentalist terrorists are thus not alone in issuing FATWAS and declaring JIHAD. Standing on the brink of this new war, it is imperative for the anti-war movement to confront and unmask religious fundamentalism. My proposal, at this stage only a conjecture, to which I welcome your critical response, is that Hegel can help us understand what we are up against with his discussion of the "third attitude of thought toward objectivity" in his SMALLER LOGIC (para. 61-78).*

HEGEL'S CRITIQUE OF INTUITIONISM

Raya Dunayevskaya placed much emphasis on Hegel's "Third Attitude of Thought Toward Objectivity" (see THE POWER OF NEGATIVITY [PON], pp. 82-84). Hegel represented the standard-bearer of this attitude in the intuitionist philosophy of F.H. Jacobi (1743-1819), a philosopher Hegel considered in 1812 to be "perhaps forgotten," but whose resurgent popularity after the post-Napoleonic Restoration of 1814-15 compelled Hegel, in 1827, to develop a category devoted to the attitude that intuitionism--the immediacy of feeling--reflected.

For Hegel, the first attitude toward objectivity is emblematically premodern--faith and scholasticism. The second attitude is modern, i.e., Empiricism and Kantian rationalism. The third attitude presupposes the second attitude and is a regressive movement in relation to it, inasmuch as it "rejects all methods" and "abandons itself to the control of a wild, capricious and fantastic dogmatism--which is loudest against philosophy" (para. 77).

Hegel characterized this third attitude as a "backward movement" (para. 76), revealing to Dunayevskaya how "the Hegelian dialectic lets retrogression appear as translucent as progression and indeed makes it very nearly inevitable if one ever tries to escape regression by mere faith" (PON, p. 332). The cult of immediate feeling or intuition unmediated by critical thought lacks "the seriousness, suffering, patience, and labor of the negative" (Hegel, PHENOMENOLOGY OF SPIRIT, p. 10).

In short, Hegelian dialectics makes no claims about the inevitability of historical progress; it is quite possible to go backwards historically as well as forward. Which direction we actually go is intimately related to what attitudes we adopt, theoretically and practically, to the objective world in which we find ourselves situated. And since thinking is prima facie free, we are not necessarily fated to an attitude that happens to prevail at some particular moment, which is why the "battle of ideas," or theoretical struggle, has a practical and political significance.

Dunayevskaya recognized that the Hegelian "cunning of Reason" does not belong to a philosophy of guarantees. Hegelianism is not a grand narrative of the inevitability of historical progress. In the precarious world situation we inhabit today, there is the real and palpable possibility that we will not go forward into the future charted by the idea of freedom. While virtually everyone on the Left adopts the rhetoric of the "liberation struggle," there is no assurance that an authentic philosophy of liberation is the project of that rhetoric.

NEW CHALLENGES FACING THE LEFT

Let's begin by considering just what world circumstances the Left is up against today. First, there is the shared leftist consensus that the momentum of the world-historical stage presently belongs to a movement of "globalization from above." Second, the counter-movement from below and from within the globalizing centers of the U.S. and Europe had begun to gather enormous momentum with the Seattle protests in the fall of 1999.

Third, however, came September 11, 2001, and the subsequent U.S.-led drive to permanent war, and the scenes of mass protest on the streets of U.S. cities have for the moment visibly diminished.

What NEWS & LETTERS has consistently observed is the troubling silence of many on the Left about the very real world-historical threat of the Islamic fundamentalism that carried out the September 11 attacks. And so we could have predicted what N&L has also consistently observed, the erosion in the U.S. of the momentum represented by Seattle in the immediate aftermath of September 11, as Bush's popularity has soared.

Also N&L has not failed to point out the link between Islamic fundamentalism (the September 11 terrorist attack, bin Laden and Al Qaeda, the Taliban, and so forth) and the third attitude towards objectivity.

This logical category of Hegelian dialectics has enormous explanatory power in directing everyone's attention to the critique of fundamentalism, regarding which too many on the Left have been equivocal. This reticence is easy enough to explain by a binary logic that takes U.S.-led imperialism to be the enemy, and which therefore concludes that any force opposed to U.S.-led imperialism is, if not precisely a friend, then a tendency that at least merits sympathy and understanding.

To the dumbed-down question, "Why do they hate us?," there has come from some quarters the dumbed-down answer, "We made them do it." There are a great many problems with this Manichean thinking, but at least two are immediately relevant here: first, it imagines that "Empire" is so overawing that spontaneous political movements around the world could not emerge of their own accord; second, it seriously underestimates just how vicious and reactionary fundamentalism really is.

At first blush, the focus might seem to be merely on Islamic fundamentalism as the object of critique, but it would be a dialectical mistake to fix on the adjective and more fundamentally fail to incorporate the noun into the third attitude toward objectivity.

N&L's support of the Revolutionary Association of the Women of Afghanistan's tour in the U.S. after September 11 bespeaks both the universality of its feminist commitments and also its recognition that "women as Reason" all over the world are capable of responding as women to their own oppression, true even when the U.S. was backing the forces that swept the Taliban into power.

But there is a mistaken, particularist way to tell the story that might go something like this: The Islamic world was subject to imperial conquest and colonial domination from without; it did not ask for the modernity that was imposed upon it. If not for conquest and domination, a non-European development of Islamic civilization (the heterogeneity of which I do not intend to oversimplify, extending as it does from Nigeria to Indonesia) might have proceeded on its own course.

CONFRONTING ISLAMIC FUNDAMENTALISM

The "anti-western" sentiments that pervade the Islamic world are therefore a function of its struggle to maintain its own cultural identity and otherness in the face of "western" imposition. But focusing the issue on the identity politics of Islam not only reduces something called "Islam" itself to a monolith, but runs the risk of obscuring a vital global kinship among fundamentalisms, the obscurity of which would also prevent theorists from developing a more comprehensive dialectical perspective.

The better place to begin is with the notion that fundamentalists are not "traditional" in the sense of wanting to take people back to the past. Numerous feminists and other writers have pointed out the ways in which the fundamentalist utopia is a modern invention. The modern reassertion by means of dogmatism and authoritarianism of a tradition that has already been historically eclipsed is what makes "fundamentalism" a modern, and not a premodern, non-western phenomenon.

Fundamentalist dogmatism and authoritarianism are reactionary, and they fall under the third attitude toward objectivity because they assert a privileged immediate knowledge of a putative truth immunized from critical scrutiny and therefore stepping back from dialectical mediation.

Since nothing can be true this way, however, the only way such self-assertion of privilege can be maintained is through terror, already implicit in bringing the charge of heresy (whether the terrorism in question is an individual act, or "state-sponsored," or straightforwardly statist).

Once this understanding of fundamentalism according to the third attitude toward objectivity comes into play, a more comprehensive dialectical perspective opens up that discloses the essential link between Bush and Bin Laden, and between Ariel Sharon and the suicide-bomber. That is, it is fundamentalism per se that fosters terrorism, whether the shape of terror is the September 11 attack, or the indiscriminate killing of Palestinian and Israeli citizens, or the Taliban's reign of terror inflicted on Afghan women, or the "collateral damages" that will continue to mount from the drive toward permanent war.

BUSH'S FUNDAMENTALISM

The cogency of this analysis presupposes that Bush is a fundamentalist, but that goes without saying. His administration should be analyzed within the framework of the Christian Right's successful reversal of the emancipatory forward ground that was gained in what seems like another age, the 1960s.

Since both Christian and Islamic fundamentalism are thoroughly patriarchal and racist (remember Bob Jones University?), since Christian fundamentalists now occupy the U.S. administration without apology, and since the Left in the U.S. has at least been knocked off balance by September 11 and its aftermath, an unequivocal critique of fundamentalism must become a crucial element in left opposition. Many voices on the Left seem momentarily paralyzed, having stopped short at first negation.

Many working people in the U.S. are understandably put off by a left opposition that cannot bring itself to oppose Islamic fundamentalist terrorism as straightforwardly as the homegrown variety represented, for example, by Timothy McVeigh. But as always in U.S. history, the vanguard of opposition domestically can be found in the Black dimension and in the ongoing struggles of women's liberation, where the critiques of racism and patriarchy are most vital when it comes to fundamentalism, and where the visionary transcendence of both is still most alive.

Having mentioned "first negation," it is worthwhile noticing that a politics that stops short here is also an undialectical politics, bereft of dialectical mediation. But the THOUGHTFUL rejection of dialectical mediation is tantamount to the third attitude towards objectivity.

In a recent letter, a friend wrote that the point in Hegel's critique of Jacobi was that Jacobi's doctrine of immediate knowledge or faith that takes whatever is found in immediate consciousness for the truth offered a shortcut, whereas there is no shortcut. The strategy of the shortcut, also when it is a strategy of opposition, is bound to be reactionary rather than progressive.

And so we cannot conceptualize the triumph of the Christian Right in U.S. politics without also conceptualizing the defeat of the "New Left" of what seems like an age ago. That Left's fascination with spontaneity, with making it up as it went along, its activism for activism's sake, and its deeply anti-theoretical posture (already betokening "postmodernism") must today also be confessed to be integral parts of its defeat a generation ago, as they will be again if the third attitude toward objectivity is not thematized and its implications forthrightly stated for our dangerous and precarious time.

*All paragraph references are to Hegel's LOGIC, Part 1 of his ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).

Return to top


Home l News & Letters Newspaper l Back issues l News and Letters Committees l Dialogues l Raya Dunayevskaya l Contact us l Search

Subscribe to News & Letters

Published by News and Letters Committees
Designed and maintained by  Internet Horizons