|
NEWS & LETTERS, November 2002
Philosophic DialogueToward a dialectical humanist ecology
by Joe Swoboda There are a number of reasons why I am excited by the
release of Joel Kovel's new book THE ENEMY OF NATURE. The first stems from my
long-held belief that Marx's humanism contains an implicit (if not explicit)
ecological dimension. Shortly after my "'conversion"' to
Marxist-Humanism in the late 1980s, which was largely the result of my reading
Marx's 1844 ECONOMIC AND PHILOSOPHIC MANUSCRIPTS, it occurred to me that though
Marx had done a wonderful job of describing man's/woman's alienation from
his/her labor, from the product of his/her labor and from other men and women
under capitalism, Marx had hinted at, but did not develop, the theory of
alienation as it related to the splitting of men/women from this thing we have
come to call "Nature." I felt the 1844 MANUSCRIPTS (and other of Marx's most
important works) were ripe for an ecological interpretation. I feel Kovel has
finally taken up this project, and I would argue that chapters 3, 5 and 6 of THE
ENEMY OF NATURE are the best attempts at connecting Marx's humanism with an
ecological vision. My second interest in Kovel's book derives from my hope
that it might provide some philosophic vision to the green movement. Like Kovel,
I am a member of the green movement and the Green Party. I joined the Green
Party in the Summer of 2001 because I saw that many young people and people who
had not otherwise been involved in left activism were being drawn to this new
political movement. When I discovered there was a Green Party local active in
the Latino immigrant community in which I live, I was also excited by the
potential for community-based organizing around issues like housing,
gentrification, and immigrants rights. However I joined with strong reservations. Most
prominent among them was my awareness that the Green Party was a reformist
organization aimed at working mostly within the confines of the established
political process and was therefore self-limiting. I was well aware of the fact
that the Green Party could easily become as much a part of the problem as had
European social democracy, especially without a more revolutionary vision. This
had already happened with the Greens in Europe. THE NEED FOR PHILOSOPHY Kovel has tried to provide the green movement with a
philosophy of revolution that points beyond purely electoral green politics.
Chapters 7, 8 and 9 of the work address this issue most particularly. There is another reason that a work like Kovel's is
important at the current moment. There are two grim possibilities facing us
currently and two potentially great movements that have arisen in response to
this situation. The push toward complete corporate world domination (i.e.
globalization) has been met with an exciting, if poorly named,
anti-globalization movement. Likewise, a new stage of permanent warfare seems to
be the likely outcome of the current "war on terrorism." This has been
met with a renewed anti-war movement. Both of these movements suffer from a
serious lack of theoretical perspective and humanist principals. With the anti-globalization movement, the problem lies
in its pragmatism. A broad-based movement involving every shade of the left from
the labor bureaucracy to youth anarchists, it has generally avoided developing
any kind of philosophic perspective. The only serious attempt at an anti-globalist
philosophy has been Hardt and Negri's EMPIRE--a great book with serious flaws.
Kovel's work does a better job addressing many of the issues Hardt and Negri
neglect--the reality of state-capitalism and the failure of so-called 20th
century "communism" being one of the most important. In the case of the anti-war movement it is more a dearth
of any humanist vision. The most unprincipled and reactionary of left political
ideas have seemed to find their home in this movement. What Kovel attempts to
offer us is a much-needed philosophy of revolution, and one grounded in the
fertile soil of ecosocialism. THE LOGIC OF CAPITAL Kovel wishes to prove that capitalism is inherently
anti-ecological. He tries to make the case that capitalism is the
"efficient cause" of the present ecological crisis. Kovel's primary
argument is that it is in capital's nature to "grow or die" and that
this endless process of self-expansion pushes beyond the ecological limits that
are necessary for stable ecosystems. He also argues that at the root of this
crisis is the domination of exchange over use-value and the transformation of
human beings and other elements of nature into exchangeable commodities. He
writes in chapter 3 (pp. 39-40) that capital represents that regime in which
exchange-value predominates over use-value in the production of commodities--and
the problem with capital is that, once installed, this process becomes
self-perpetuating and self-expanding. The process entails a twofold degradation. In the first
place, "We have the commodification of nature, which includes human beings,
and their bodies," Kovel writes. "However... nature simply does
not work in this way. No matter what capital's ideologues say, the actual laws
of nature never include monetization; they exist, rather, in the context of
ecosystems whose internal relations are violated by conversion to the
money-form. Thus the ceaseless rendering into commodities, with its monetization
and exchange, breaks down the specificity and intricacy of ecosystems. To this
is added the devaluation, or basic lack of caring, which attends what is left
over and unprofitable. Here arise the so-called 'externalities' that become
repositories of pollution." Kovel's argument that capitalist self-expansion is
ecologically unsustainable is easily made. As he points out, even bourgeois
ecologists have called for "limits to growth," seemingly
uncomprehending that limits are anathema to capital and that capital will always
extend commodity production past any limitations in order to survive. He uses a couple of eco-catastrophes to illustrate this.
The most important is the 1984 tragedy at the Union Carbide plant in Bhopal,
India. Kovel does an admirable job of explaining how this "industrial
accident," which resulted in the death of over 8,000 people, was ultimately
a product of the logic of capital and not just an isolated incident. He also points out that the plant's very existence in
Bhopal was the result of the ecologically devastating "green
revolution" of the 1970's, which foisted dependence on pesticides upon the
developing world. The case is perhaps better made by his critique of the
culture of "automobilia." Kovel describes how automobile production
has created a situation where its "limitation" or lack of growth as an
industry would create a global economic crisis but its continual expansion
creates massive ecological devastation worldwide. He also points out how the
production of this single commodity results in and feeds on the warping of human
needs/desires while deepening the process of alienation. Unfortunately, Kovel's historical case examples could be
stronger. Other ecologists and ecological historians--William Cronon is one who
comes to mind--have done a better job of capturing how commodity production
transforms human and "natural" communities. Indeed, Kovel's
"science" is at times a bit too simplistic, as when he explains that
his interest in global warming was originally sparked by one exceptionally hot
summer in which his home garden was laid to waste. The strength of Kovel's work is not in its description
of the impact of capital on ecosystems. Instead, its brilliance is in
understanding how alienation is at the root of capitalism's eco-destructive
character and that only by overcoming this alienation in its multifaceted forms
can a society of ecological "sufficiency" be achieved. ECOSOCIALISM & DIALECTICAL HUMANISM What makes Kovel's ecosocialist vision so exciting is
that it is firmly grounded in Marx's humanist philosophy and dialectics--which
Marx himself described as a "fully-developed naturalism" and a
"resolution of the antagonism between man/woman and nature" in the
1844 MANUSCRIPTS. This is evident early on in the work, when Kovel explains why
his philosophy is based on an ecological and not environmental perspective: "The environment is by definition a set of things
outside us, with no essential structure, while an ecology is a whole DEFINED BY
INTERNAL RELATIONS. Environments can be listed and numerically evaluated.
Ecologies offer no such packaging and the boundaries between them are sites of
active transformation, without a fixed line between inside and outside. In
particular, the boundary between humanity and nature becomes highly dynamic, and
a matter to be understood historically and transformed politically" (p.
17). Though the focus of much of the work is on the "grow or die"
nature of capitalism, Kovel is careful to avoid a narrow "economistic"
interpretation of this phenomenon. For Kovel, the imperative to self-expansion
is inherently linked to alienated labor, the heart of the capitalist production
system: "It follows that the ecological crisis is not
simply a manifestation of the macro-economic effects of capital, but also
reveals the extension of capitalist alienation into the ecosphere. And as this
alienation, and the whole structure of the system, is grounded in the relation
between capital and labor, it also follows that the ecological crisis and
capital's exploitation of labor are two aspects of the same phenomenon" (p.
132). Kovel continually points out that
"Separation/alienation/splitting is the fundamental gesture of
capital" and that "the phenomenon of separation expresses the core
gesture of eco-disintegration" (pp. 131-32). Indeed, the concept of nature
as a static, quantifiable other, separated from humanity, is a part of this
alienation and at the core of our society's anti-ecological character. Such a notion of the environment even infects "ecophilosophies"
such as deep ecology and bioregionalism. Kovel argues that only in overcoming
this alienation can ecosocialism be achieved: "Recognition of ourselves in nature and nature in
ourselves, in other words subjective as well as objective participation in
ecosystems, is the essential condition for overcoming the domination of nature,
and its pathologies of instrumental production and addictive consumption"
(p. 209). Central to this alienation is what Kovel refers to as
the "gendered bifurcation of nature." In chapter 6, he develops a sort
of anthropology of man's estrangement from nature, in many ways similar to the
ideas of the social ecologist Murray Bookchin. Kovel points out that male
domination is integrally related not only to the development of the concepts of
property and production relations in human history, but also to the identifying
of nature as an Other to be manipulated and subjugated—a female other (p.
121). This aspect of Kovel's analysis is particularly
interesting and insightful and I praise him for making women's exploitation, a
central component of his ecophilosophy. However it also presents an almost
essentialist notion of men as the violent victimizers and women as passive
victims lacking full subjectivity. Interestingly, Kovel attacks Bookchin's similar
anthropology of estrangement for focusing too much on the issue of hierarchy as
the fundamental moment in the process. I find Bookchin's description of
humanity's struggle to overcome it's domination by natural forces, which leads
to humanity's domination of nature, somewhat more consistent and historically
grounded than Kovel's. Indeed, I was interested to hear more of Kovel's critique
of the philosophy of social ecology, but the few pages he devotes to the subject
in chapter 7 focus too much on the supposed shortcomings of Bookchin the person
rather than the movement itself. I find myself disagreeing with Kovel when he places
social ecology alongside neo-Smithians under the rubric of community-based
economics, and in his claim that critiques of hierarchy and the state don't
deserve the central importance they are given by social ecologists and the
anarchist tradition. THE WORK'S GREATEST WEAKNESS This brings me to what is the most important weakness in
Kovel's work. He attempts to apply Marx's brilliant dialectical methodology to
the understanding of the current ecological crisis. For the most part, he is
quite successful, particularly when illustrating how alienation is at its root.
But Marx's dialectical vision captured not only the crisis and process of
domination, but also focused on the subjects of revolt, the forces of freedom,
that inevitably arose from this same process. Kovel has not developed this side of the dialectic
fully. Though he makes it quite clear that the domination of nature is
integrally related to the alienation of labor and the subjugation of women, he
does not fully investigate how these human subjects become agents of the new
struggle for freedom. Many readers I have spoken to feel that the weakest
chapters of Kovel's book are the final two. Often they are referred to as a
laundry list or a wish list, or as overly formulaic or utopian. I agree and
would argue that this stems from a lack of an organic relationship in the book
between the objective crisis and the subjects of revolt. Others have pointed out that Kovel has little discussion
about the environmental justice movement that has arisen in many
African-American and Latino working class communities in recent years. Perhaps
if Kovel had spent more time examining these movements, the subjective side of
the dialectic would have been more fully grasped and a more thoroughly
revolutionary outlook could have been provided in the last chapters. A philosophy of revolution is not the same as a
blueprint for revolution, and when intellectuals are not firmly connected to the
masses in revolt, what often results are utopian schemes rather than
revolutionary vision. The big question remains, does THE ENEMY OF NATURE
represent a breakthrough for an ecologically grounded philosophy of revolution
that can inform not only the green movement, but also other key social movements
in the current period? I would have to conclude that it is certainly a major step in the right direction. Kovel's development of the ecological potential of Marx's humanist dialectics is brilliant and long overdue. It represents a philosophic perspective that has been seriously lacking in green politics, though his analysis of how to integrate the two is less than satisfactory. I would be very interested to see a dialogue between Kovel, NEWS & LETTERS and the social ecologists, as I think each could offer the others great insights on developing a more complete revolutionary philosophy. But certainly the greatest challenge and the greatest test will be how well Kovel's work resonates with the needs, hopes, and ideas of those who will ultimately rise up to challenge capitalism's eco-suicide. |
Home l News & Letters Newspaper l Back issues l News and Letters Committees l Dialogues l Raya Dunayevskaya l Contact us l Search Published by News and Letters Committees |