www.newsandletters.org












NEWS & LETTERS, January-February 2002

Column: Woman as Reason by Maya Jhansi

A case of philosophical sexism?

On Saturday, Jan. 19, I went to the launch party for the new book THE POWER OF NEGATIVITY: SELECTED WRITINGS ON THE DIALECTIC IN HEGEL AND MARX (Lexington Books, 2002). This is a new collection of Raya Dunayevskaya's writings on dialectical philosophy, edited by Peter Hudis and Kevin Anderson. As the speakers presented their views of this book, it occurred to me that one of the most unique things about Dunayevskaya is the way she jams together dialectical philosophy and gender.

For the most part, feminists who are interested in socialist feminism are not interested in Hegelian dialectics, and those who write about the Hegel-Marx connection tend to ignore feminism. Ian Fraser and Tony Burns' new book, THE HEGEL-MARX CONNECTION, is a good example of the latter. It brings together an array of writings on the Hegel-Marx connection.

However, not only does the book not have a single essay by a woman, Fraser and Burns fail to mention Dunayevskaya at all in their introduction, a historical synopsis of the different approaches to the Hegel-Marx connection, even though no other American Marxist has written so extensively on the subject. This is not to mention that Dunayevskaya is often a lone voice in her insistence that Hegelian dialectics is needed for a feminist rethinking of Marxism.

It is hard to see Fraser and Burns' omission as anything other than sexism, though when you look at their introduction, it becomes clear why they left Dunayevskaya out.

THE MATERIALIST TRAP

Fraser and Burns break down the attitude to Hegel into two main camps, those who saw Marx as appropriating Hegel's dialectic and those who wanted to expunge Hegel from Marx. They begin their survey with the young Marx's writings on Hegel, and then move on to Engels and his influence over orthodox Marxism. They summarize the ways that Engels' understanding came to dominate orthodox Marxist views of the Hegel-Marx connection.

In the late 1850s Marx had planned to write a short book on Hegel's philosophy, but never did so. It became easier to take Engels word on the dialectic, than to do the "labor, patience and suffering of the negative" to hear Marx think. Engels is the one who popularized this idea that Marx "inverted" Hegel, that he turned Hegel around on his feet. To Engels, dialectical philosophy is merely the "reflection" of the dialectics of reality "in the thinking brain."

Fraser and Burns go over those who challenged the Engelsian view of the Hegel-Marx connection by taking up the Hegelian dimension of Marx's philosophy, such as Lenin, Lukács, Marcuse, Kojève, Lefebvre, Sartre—but, of course no mention of Dunayevskaya, who challenged Engelsian distortions of Marx's dialectics and of Marx's views on gender. They then turn to those like Althusser, Colletti, Della Volpe who wanted to "drive Hegel into the night" as Althusser once put it. Fraser and Burns, however, reject both camps.

Their answer to the battle between Hegelian and anti-Hegelian Marxists is that "there is no need for Marxists to appropriate a modified, materialist version of Hegel's philosophical idealism into their own thought. For Marx's 'materialism' can be derived directly from Hegel's own social thought without any such adaptation or modification." To Fraser and Burns, Hegel is himself a materialist and, in some sense, a "Marxist."

They raise Hegel's political writings above his philosophical writings—calling it his "Realphilosophie." Hegel and Marx's dialectic, they argue, "are one and the same. The historical opposition between idealism and materialism, and the influence which it has had upon our understanding of the intellectual relationship between Hegel and Marx is, on this reading, overcome by stressing the thoroughgoing 'materialism' of Hegel's own dialectic."

Although Fraser and Burns are attempting to do away with the opposition between materialism and idealism, they are in fact recapitulating it by ignoring the importance of Hegel's "idealism," which Marx credited with developing the "active side" of human subjectivity. They are, in fact, victim to the post-Marx Marxist aversion to philosophy.

UNITY OF THEORY AND PRACTICE

On the contrary, Dunayevskayadid not reduce Hegel to a materialist. A quote from Hegel's SMALLER LOGIC speaks to this: "The notion that ideas and ideals are nothing but chimeras, and that philosophy is a system of pure phantasms, sets itself at once against the actuality of what is rational; but, conversely, the notion that ideas and ideals are something far too excellent to have actuality, or equally too impotent to have actuality, is opposed to it as well. This science deals only with the Idea—which is not so impotent that it merely ought to be, and is not actual." To Hegel, ideascan't be dismissed as chimeras. At the same time the Idea itself has actuality.

This is what Dunayevskaya stressed in her writings on dialectics. To her, the Women's Liberation Movement was evidence of the existence of the Idea in reality, but it was not enough by itself, as we are experiencing right now. "A movement from theory to practice" is needed as well, she argued.

Dunayevskaya's writings challenge both the neat division Fraser and Burns make between the Hegelian and anti-Hegelian Marxists, and their so-called "solution" to the problem. This is perhaps why they did not see fit to include her in their overview. Or perhaps it is something more common, the sexist deafness in the world of Marxist philosophy to women's ideas, except as tokens to talk about gender. In either case, THE POWER OF NEGATIVITY gives us new insights into dialectics that might help us bridge the current gulf between feminist and dialectical philosophy.

Return to top


Home l News & Letters Newspaper l Back issues l News and Letters Committees l Dialogues l Raya Dunayevskaya l Contact us l Search

Subscribe to News & Letters

Published by News and Letters Committees
Designed and maintained by  Internet Horizons