Essay article
December 2000
Marx's CRITIQUE OF THE GOTHA PROGRAM, 125 years later
by Mitch Weerth
Karl Marx penned his CRITIQUE OF THE GOTHA PROGRAM 125 years ago. This
anniversary, however, is not the main reason to study this document.
Rather, the need to seriously grapple with it today is occasioned by our
desire to work out an alternative to capital.
In previous issues of NEWS & LETTERS we have shown the error of those in
the protests against the new stage of globalization who believe in
humanity's ability to control capital (see especially "Can Capital be
Controlled?" April 2000 N&L). The question to be posed here is: how can we
be convinced, and in turn convince others, that a new society based on a
conscious collective effort to reevaluate and satisfy human needs can
prevail over the current trampling of humanity and the environment at the
service of the self-expansion of value?
Marx's CRITIQUE speaks directly to this in three principal ways: 1) In its
historical context it reveals the kinds of difficulties Marx's
contemporaries had in basing an organization on his theories. 2) Its
theoretical content is a profound critique of "socialist ideas that are not
even skin-deep," in other words, that which to this day usually pass for
"Marxism." 3) Its strictly philosophical content reveals unresolved
problems that today's generation is faced with working out.
THE 'UNITY' AT GOTHA
The recipients of what Marx called his "critical marginal notes" on the
Gotha Program were the leaders of Germany's Social-Democratic Workers Party
(SDAP, known as the "Eisenachers").
This party, with a little over 9,000 members in 1875, was formed in 1869 in
the city of Eisenach. Its program declared itself to be a branch of Marx's
International Workingman's Association (IWA), "adhering to its
aspirations." It formed in opposition to the General Association of German
Workers (ADAV, "Lassalleans" with about 15,000 members in 1875), founded by
Ferdinand Lassalle 15 months before his death in 1864.
While Marx acknowledged Lassalle's contribution in organizing the first
independent mass political organization of workers in Germany, he also
criticized his attitude as being that of a future "workers' dictator." This
was due to Lassalle's fruitless reliance on the Prussian state to bring
about socialism "from above."
Marx's CRITIQUE is largely a critique of Lassalle's doctrines as expressed
in the program that was drawn up to unite the two parties at a congress in
the city of Gotha in 1875. The tragedy is that the program was authored not
by the Lassalleans but by an Eisenacher, Wilhelm Liebknecht. (Eisenachers
were considered Marxists due to their opposition to "state-sponsored
socialism," familiarity with Marx's ideas and closer relationship to the
IWA.)
Liebknecht was not prodded by his enemies to write a program that mirrored
their ideas. He was so eager to unite the factions at any cost that after
sealing the deal in a small meeting with ADAV leaders in December 1874
(this was prior to the unity congress and it excluded the SDAP's firmest
critics of Lassallean doctrine), he wrote to Engels that his program meant
"the complete victory of 'Marxian' communism over Lassallean sectarianism.
And to achieve this victory, I would have been prepared for still further
concessions."
The "victory" he refers to is the fact that the new party that emerged from
the unity, the German Social Democracy, adopted the more democratic
organizational structure of the SDAP in place of the dictatorial form
Lassalle gave the ADAV. Liebknecht was absolutely certain that "free debate
in such an organization would eventually eradicate the Lassallean
misconceptions."
From the perspective of Marx's CRITIQUE it's hard to imagine what "further
concessions" he could have made. But despite them, the unity was indeed
seen as a victory by nearly all. August Bebel, an SDAP leader who tried and
failed to correct some of the program's errors at the congress itself,
expressed in his memoirs (written in 1910) a sentiment still heard today:
"It was no easy task toagree with the two old men in London [Marx and
Engels]. What we saw as clever calculation, adept tactics, they saw as
weakness and irresponsible complaisance; ultimately, the fact of the
unification was the main point."
It was not "the main point" for Marx, and on this he stood alone. Even
Engels, who dutifully attacked the Gotha Program, was ambiguous about the
merger itself. He was certain that it would lead to a new split (which it
didn't) and wrote that it "may be considered a great success if it holds
out for two years" as an "educational experiment" for both parties.
ORGANIZATION AND PHILOSOPHY
István Mészáros, author of BEYOND CAPITAL is one of the few who have looked
at Marx's CRITIQUE as an organizational document. He seems to side with
Marx when he writes: "...if the socialist revolution is seen as primarily
political in character, rather than as a multidimensional, and therefore
necessarily 'permanent' social revolution, as Marx defined it, in that
case...unity overrides everything in importance." To counter such "mania
for unity" Mészáros proposes "socialist pluralism."
This approach, while "agreeing" with Marx, seems to repeat the error of
Liebknecht, and on a less vulgar level, Engels: that of assuming
ideological differences will resolve themselves when placed in the right
organizational framework. Marx, however, did not think there could be a
strictly ORGANIZATIONAL answer to a CONCEPTUAL problem. If he did, he would
simply have confined his criticism by pointing out, as he does in his cover
letter, that his followers "surrender unconditionally to those who are in
need of help."
The CRITIQUE, on the other hand, is a critique of an organizational
document. The meaning of this simple fact seems to have been lost on
Marxists for generations. For while history has shown that any
organization, no matter how large, will loose course without a
philosophical rudder directed to the spirit of the times, "history" has
failed to give us an example of the integrality of the two worked out as a
living "revolution in permanence."
MARX'S 'MARGINAL NOTES'
To begin to get a handle on the problem requires, first, a thorough study
of the CRITIQUE itself. Here we will have to limit ourselves to a few of
its main points.
To the very first words of the program: "Labor is the source of all
wealth..." Marx responds: "Labor is NOT THE SOURCE of all wealth. NATURE is
just as much the source of use values...as is labor..." Leaving nature out
of the equation to Marx meant "ascribing SUPERNATURAL CREATIVE POWER," a
typical ploy of the ruling class in whose interest it is to maintain their
hold on the means of production.
As with most of the content of the CRITIQUE, this first paragraph is little
appreciated by Marxists and non-Marxists to this day. Environmentalists
will shun Marx because his supposed sole focus on labor automatically
results in the wasting of nature, while Marxists eager to set the record
straight likewise abstract from the total environment Marx situated the
human subject in. As far back as 1844 he had written: "Just as completed
humanism is naturalism, so this communism, as completed naturalism, is
humanism." The affirmation of the one is likewise an affirmation of the
other.
Related to this is Marx's objection to using other vague economic
categories in an attempt to anticipate precise social relations that emerge
with the overthrow of capitalism. This is the case with the Gotha Program's
call for the "undiminished proceeds of labor" to be distributed with "equal
right" to all members of society.
In total contradiction to all those who attempt to pin the label of
"socialism" on one or another state-capitalist society, from Stalin's
Russia to Castro's Cuba, stands Marx's insistence here that the law of
value ceases right FROM THE START of the new society. He writes: "Within
the co-operative society...the producers do not exchange their products;
just as little does the labor employed on the products appear here as the
VALUE of these products, as a material quality possessed by them..."
In no uncertain terms Marx is telling us here that from day one after the
revolution labor-power will no longer appear in the shape of a commodity,
bought and sold at value. There is nothing "transitional" about this aspect
of socialism. What is undeveloped at the early stage is the fact that what
the worker receives back from society, after necessary deductions for
administration, health services, etc., is exactly what he gives to it: "The
same amount of labor which he has given to society in one form, he receives
back in another."
"Equal right," in this sense is to Marx still "a right of inequality in its
content, like every right," since all are seen only as workers, and we
abstract from their real needs (one has more children than another, etc.)
From this insight he projects the goal not of "equal right" but a society
that would leave behind this "narrow horizon" and inscribe on its banner:
"From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs."
What is so remarkable is that nearly every "Marxist" bows down to this
concept as the "ultimate" that we all strive for yet disregards the fact
that it flows from the sharpest critique of their own most dearly held
"socialist" theory (whether admitted or not): that of the law of value
operates within socialism.
NATIONALISM AND INTERNATIONALISM
The concepts in the CRITIQUE are so au courant and interrelated that they
speak in a most direct way to another burning issue of today that radicals
are far from having in the marrow of their bones: internationalism.
Lassalle had written: "I allow the right of being a nation only to the
great civilized peoples; to be assimilated by these is the only right I
allow to the others." The Gotha Program follows him by claiming that
workers struggle "first of all within the framework of the present-day
national state." Marx attacks this formulation by pointing out that the
German empire is "economically 'within the framework' of the world market,
politically 'within the framework' of the system of states."
The "international functions" of the working class, according to the
CRITIQUE, is precisely what breaks from this bourgeois "framework." Yet how
many "Marxists" today refuse to support the right of Kosova to break from
Serbia, some on the basis of Serbia being "socialist," some on the basis of
the Kosovars themselves not decidedly enough aiming for "socialism"?
It should not surprise us that this document points up the many glaring
limitations of what passes for "Marxism" today. What still needs to be
answered, however, is the question we began with: can it help to work out
an alternative to capital?
ALTERNATIVES TO CAPITAL
Based on the content discussed above, the answer should be an emphatic
"yes." This was the first time anywhere that Marx had ventured to give an
idea of what the new society would look like, from its initial stages to a
time when labor would develop from being a "mere means of life" to "the
prime necessity of life." Isn't this the very unifying element the
different social movements of today are so in need of?
On the other hand, what seems to have been skipped over even by those who
haven't made the obvious blunders already mentioned, is the significance of
a clear philosophic articulation of a "higher phase" of communism appearing
only in 1875, and ONLY IN AN ORGANIZATIONAL DOCUMENT. Spontaneous,
"pluralist" forms are always getting counterposed to the vanguardist,
centralized forms while in the heat of the moment Marx's philosophy drops
out of sight.
Raya Dunayevskaya was the first to analyze Marx's CRITIQUE as an
organizational document. What is compelling about her view is that she
didn't see the CRITIQUE as being the last word on the subject. In two of
her last writings on what she called "dialectics of organization and
philosophy," written shortly before her death in 1987, she took up none
other than Hegel, supposedly the most "idealist" of philosophers, to look
deeper into the problem (these were included in the 1989 edition of her
PHILOSOPHY AND REVOLUTION. Before we reject this as "abstract" in the manner Eisenachers rejected Marx, consider the following:
First, her original 1953 a
nalysis of Hegel's Absolutes, which enabled her to present Marxism once
again in its original form (see her 1958 MARXISM AND FREEDOM in a new 2000
edition) was occasioned precisely by her attempt to work out what she then
called "the dialectic of the party." This problem, the relationship of
revolutionary theory to mass movements, was seen as most thoroughly
illuminated by, of all things, Hegel's "Absolutes."
Second, the content of the CRITIQUE itself points us, if only implicitly,
to what Marx elsewhere called "the source of all dialectic," Hegel. We have
seen what made Marx so furious about the Gotha Program: that
revolutionaries should take a "retrograde step" in inscribing Lassallean
ideas on their banner. Over and over again in the CRITIQUE he hammers this
point home. In his covering letter he called it the "sanctification of the
Lassallean articles of faith." Was it not precisely Hegel who, after
completing his major works, referred to the reappearance of Jacobi's
intuitionist philosophy of faith as a "reactionary" phenomenon?
It could be that none of the Marxists saw the need to build on Marx's
concept of uniting philosophy and organization because they had no idea how
deeply rooted the problem is philosophically and historically. Today we
can't make that excuse.
|