From the Writings of Raya Dunayevskaya: Marxist-Humanist
Archives
March 1999
Rough Notes on Hegel's SCIENCE OF LOGIC
Part 2: Doctrine of Being
by Raya Dunayevskaya, founder of Marxist-Humanism in the U.S.
Editor's Note: The following consists of Part 2 of Raya
Dunayevskaya's detailed commentary on Hegel's SCIENCE OF LOGIC.
Part 1, on the Prefaces and Introduction to the LOGIC, appeared
in our January-February issue. Parts 3 and 4, on the Doctrine of
Essence and the Doctrine of the Notion, will appear in the April
and May issues, respectively. These notes were written in 1961
and appear in print for the first time.
The LOGIC is one of Hegel's most important works and was of
great service to Marx, especially in the writing of CAPITAL. It
has taken on new importance in light of the need to comprehend
the logic of contemporary capitalism and the struggles against
it. These notes will serve as an anchor of a nationwide series
of classes News and Letters Committees will soon hold on
"The Dialectic of Marx's CAPITAL and Today's Global
Crisis." To find out about how to participate in them, see
the announcement on page 11, or contact the News and Letters
Committee nearest you (see page 7).
All material in brackets as well as footnotes have been supplied
by the editors. "SLI" and "SLII" refer to
the text of the SCIENCE OF LOGIC as translated by Johnston and
Struthers, in two volumes (Macmillan, 1929); "SLM"
refers to the translation by A.V. Miller (Humanities Press,
1969). The references to Lenin are to his 1914-15 commentary on
Hegel's LOGIC, the first such study done by a Marxist.
Dunayevskaya's text has been slightly shortened, indicated by
the use of ellipses. The original can be found in THE RAYA
DUNAYEVSKAYA COLLECTION, 2806.
We are finally ready to begin Book One, but we better
remember the broad outline of the whole LOGIC into two volumes,
Objective Logic and Subjective Logic; more definitely, it has
three parts, namely: 1) The Logic of Being, 2) The Logic of
Essence, and 3) The Logic of the Notion.
Book One: The Doctrine of Being
Section One: Determinateness (Quality)
Chapter I: Being
There are only three short paragraphs in chapter I on Being,
Nothing and Becoming, whereupon Hegel goes into no less than
five Observations which stretch over 25 pages, which, in fact,
cover very nearly the whole of preceding philosophies, from the
Orient through the Greeks to his own time on this question of
Being. Thus: OBSERVATION ONE—the Opposition of Being and
Nothing in Imagination contrasts Parmenides' "pure
enthusiasm of thought first comprehending itself in its absolute
abstraction" to Buddhism where "Nothing or Void is the
absolute principle," to Heraclitus, whose opposition to
both one-sided abstractions of Being and Nothing led to the
total concept of Becoming: "All things flow," which
means everything is Becoming [SLI, pp. 95-96; SLM, p. 83].
But Hegel does not stop either with the Orient or with the
Greeks, but proceeds to consider Spinoza, as well as the Kantian
Critique. Not only that, it's quite obvious that both in
philosophy and in science Hegel is the historical materialist:
"What is first in science has had to show itself first too,
historically" [SLI, p. 101; SLM, p. 88].
If Observation One dealt with the Unity of Being and Nothing
as Becoming in a profound manner, Hegel hurries to criticize
this, too, in OBSERVATION TWO—The Inadequacy of the Expression
"Unity" or "Identity of Being and Nothing."
The point is that Unity "sounds violent and striking in
proportion as the objects of which it is asserted obviously show
themselves as distinct. In this respect therefore mere
Unseparateness or Inseparability would be a good substitute for
Unity; but these would not express the affirmative nature of the
relation of the whole. The whole and true result, therefore,
which has here been found, is Becoming. . ." [SLI, p. 104;
SLM, p. 91].
He, therefore, proceeds to OBSERVATION THREE—The Isolation
of these Abstractions, in order to stress that the Unity of
Being and Nothing has to be considered in a relationship to a
third, i.e., Becoming, and therefore, we must consider the
TRANSITION. Otherwise, we would constantly be evading the
internal contradictoriness, although Hegel admits that "It
would be wasted labor to spread a net for all the twistings and
objections of reflection and its reasonings, in order to cut off
and render impossible all the evasions and digressions which it
uses to hide from itself its own internal
contradictoriness" [SLI, p. 106; SLM, p. 94].
He here hits out at his two main enemies, Fichte and Jacobi,
whom he compares to the abstractions of Indian thought or the
Brahma: "this torpid and vacuous consciousness, taken as
consciousness, is Being" [SLI, p. 109; SLM, p. 97]. (With
this should be read the section on Oriental philosophy [in]
Hegel's PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. It used to annoy me very much
because I thought it showed German arrogance to Oriental
philosophy. But it is, in fact, so objective an analysis of
Hinduism that it will explain a great deal of modern India's
difficulties in stamping out castes.)
Both in the observation "Incomprehensibility of the
Beginning" and the next OBSERVATION—"The Expression
to Transcend," Hegel has shifted both the actual and the
philosophic, not alone from Being and Nothing to Becoming, but
transcended Becoming, which is the first leap forward from an
abstract being to a determinate, or specific being, with which
chapter II will deal. All we need to remember at this point is
that "what is transcended is also preserved [SLI, p. 120;
SLM, p. 107].
Chapter II: Determinate Being
The structure of LOGIC has now been set. We will at each
point, though not in as overwhelming a manner, state a fact or
proposition and then proceed to an Observation; in a word, the
polemical movement in the LOGIC follows right alongside, and
inseparably, with the affirmative statement.
You may recall that that is the form of Marxs [CONTRIBUTION
TO THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY]. As you know, he was quite
dissatisfied with the form, [and] discarded it for CAPITAL. This
was not only due to the fact that he decided that the polemical,
as history of thought rather than CLASS STRUGGLE, should all be
placed together in a separate book (Book Four).(1) That much is
obvious and would not have, in itself, produced such utter
blindness on the part of Marxists who could quite easily see
that the historical, to Marx, was not history of thought, but
history of class struggle, since, as a matter of fact, Kautskyan
popularizations dealt with the class struggle without much
concern to thought. No, it is the dialectics, the new, the
creative dialectics of the class struggle, which did not
separate philosophy—how long is my working day?—from the
class struggle, which remain a mystery to the materialists who
were so busy "opposing the mystical" in Hegel.
But the fact that the Hegelian structure could not be
"copied" by Marx, but had to be RE-created, does not
mean that the Hegelian structure FOR HEGEL was wrong. On the
contrary, he deals with thought, and the logical form of the
Universal there is the Notion.
We have moved from the Universal, General, Abstract Being to
a definite Being or Something, but this assumption of a
definitive quality immediately moves Hegel to an observation—"Quality
and Negation." "Determinateness is negation posited
affirmatively, is the meaning of Spinoza's OMNIS DETERMINATIO
EST NEGATIO [every determination is a negation], a proposition
of infinite importance; only, negation as such is formless
abstraction. Speculative philosophy must not be accused of
making negation, or Nothing, its end: Nothing is the end of
philosophy as little as Reality is the truth" [SLI, p. 125;
SLM, p. 113].
But it must not be imagined that Hegel is only arguing with
other philosophers, though that is his world. He is also moving
to ever more determinate stages of the concrete, for what
pervades everything in Hegel—everything from Absolute Idea to
the simple Something of a chair or a leaf or a seed—is his
fundamental principle that the Truth is always concrete.
Because, however, what was most concrete with him was Thought,
and because this early in the LOGIC when he deals with
Something, he is already dealing with it as "the first
negation of the negation," Lenin gets furious with him at
this point and returns to a warm feeling toward Engels by
referring to the quotation about "abstract and abstruse
Hegelianism" [LCW 38, p. 108].
And yet it is only a few short pages beyond this when dealing
with finitude and against the Kantian thing-in-itself [that]
Lenin remarks that this whole attack on the Thing-in-itself is
"very profound" and again "SEHR GUT!!" [very
good, LCW 38, pp. 110-11]. Lenin straightaway makes that
conclusion of the essence of the dialectic which he is going to
repeat throughout his reading and which will indeed become the
basis of all his writings from there on from IMPERIALISM to the
WILL.
Thus, it is near Hegel's remark against the critical
philosophy, i.e., Kant [SLI, p. 135, SLM, p. 122] that Lenin
writes: "Dialectic is the doctrine of the IDENTITY OF
OPPPOSITES—how they can be and how they become identical,
transforming one into another—why the mind of man must not
take these opposites for dead, blocked (ZASTYVAHIYE), but for
living, conditioned, mobile, transforming one into the other. EN
LISANT [in reading] Hegel. . ." [LCW 38, p. 109]. This,
mind you, is said not in Book Three on Notion, nor even in Book
Two on Essence, nor even in Section Three of Book Two on Measure
where we are "practically" ready to jump into Essence,
but in the very first section of Book One, chapter II.
At this point Hegel comments that in the question of
determination the chief point is "to distinguish what is
still IN ITSELF and what is POSITED . . . and being-for-other.
This distinction is proper only to dialectical development and
is unknown to the metaphysical (which includes the Critical)
philosophy" [SLI, p. 135; SLM, p. 122]. It is here that
Lenin has his first definition of dialectic as the doctrine of
the identity of opposites, before which generalization, he
writes: "This is very profound; the thing-in-itself and its
transformation into the thing-for-other (cf. Engels). The
thing-in-itself, IN GENERAL, is an empty, lifeless abstraction.
In life in the movement all and everything is USED to being both
'in itself' and 'for other' in relation to Other, transforming
itself from one condition (SOSTOYANIYE) to another" [LCW
38, p. 109].
Hegel proceeds next to analyze Finitude and Ought. The Ought
in turn is followed by an Observation where he tangles with
Leibniz [SLI, p. 148; SLM, p. 135] and with Kant and Fichte [SLI,
p. 149; SLM, p. 136] who, he insists, have the standpoint,
precisely because they get stuck in Ought, "where they
persist in Finitude, and (which is the same thing) in
contradiction."
Lenin is again moved here to speak about the profound
analysis Hegel makes of the Finite, saying "The Finite?
that means MOVEMENT has come to an end! Something? that means
NOT WHAT OTHER is. Being, in general? that means such
indeterminateness that Being=Not-Being. All-sided, universal
flexibility of concepts—flexibility reaching to the identity
of opposites" [LCW 38, p. 110].
In the section which follows on Infinity, the critical point
is transition: "Ideality(2) may be called the Quality of
Infinity; but, as it is essentially the process of Becoming, it
is a Transition, like that of Becoming in Determinate Being, and
it must now be indicated" [SLI, p. 163; SLM, p. 150]. Two
other observations followed this one, one on "Infinite
Progress": "Bad Infinity,"(3) says Hegel, like
progress to infinity, is really no different than Ought,
"the expression of a contradiction, which pretends to be
the solution and the ultimate" [SLI, p. 164; SLM, p. 150].
The second observation is on "Idealism," where he
contrasts Subjective and Objective Idealism, and which brings us
to Chapter III, "Being-For-Self."
Somewhere in this chapter—in fact, in the first Observation—ideality
is taken up both as it applies to Leibniz's Monads,(4) as well
as Eleatic Being,(5) and also the Atomistic philosophy,(6) and
again, there are many observations ending with the one on Kant's
"Attraction and Repulsion." Now on the one hand, Lenin
is very specific in his interpretation here, calling attention
to the fact that "the idea of the transformation of the
ideal into the real is PROFOUND; very important for history. . .
against vulgar materialism" [LCW 38, p. 114], and yet the
whole chapter on Being-For-Self, when Lenin first approaches it,
is considered by him to be "dark waters" [LCW 38, p.
114]. At this point here, during the correspondence with [C.L.R.
James] and [Grace Lee] in 1949, Grace [Lee] developed her
thoughts on this chapter as one dealing with the developing
subject as it first arose, 500 B.C., to the Absolute Idea, or
the conditions for universality of the modern proletariat. She
seemed to think that Being-For-One coming from Being-For-Self
was unclear to Lenin because he did not understand abstract
labor as we did. I doubt that was the reason since in the
Doctrine of Being, we are, comparatively, at a low stage of
development in Hegelian thought.
The fact, however, that [Hegel] can at this "low
stage" be so profound and point to so many of the
conditions which we will meet in the Absolute Idea shows that
you can, in fact, not make sharp divisions even in those most
sharply pointed to by Hegel himself—Being, Essence, Notion—as
is shown over and over again by the fact that he deals with Kant
who was the greatest philosopher before him in this very
section.
Indeed, Lenin here notes (evidently it struck him for the
first time) that the self-development of the concept in Hegel is
related to the entire history of philosophy. In any case, in the
Observation on the Unity of the One and the Many, [Hegel] deals
also with the dialectic of Plato in the PARMENIDES. What is true
is Hegel's very sharp opposition to so-called independence in
the One: "Independence having reached its quintessence in
the One which is for itself, is abstract and formal, destroying
itself; it is the highest and most stubborn error, which takes
itself for highest truth; appearing, more concretely, as
abstract freedom, pure ego, and further as Evil. It is freedom
which goes so far astray as to place its essence in this
abstraction, flattering itself that, being thus by itself, it
possesses itself in its purity" [SLI, p. 185; SLM, p. 172].
Section Two: Magnitude (Quantity)
We have first now reached the transformation of Quality or
Determinateness into Quantity, Being-For-Self having concluded
Section One, and having in turn been divided into three—Being-For-Self
as such, the One and the Many, and Repulsion and Attraction.
In the first observation on Pure Quantity, as well as in the
second observation on Kant's "Antinomy of the
Indivisibility and Infinite Divisibility of Time, Space and
Matter," the concept that we are approaching is that of
Continuous and Discrete magnitude.(7) But before he deals with
these concepts, Hegel feels he must attack not only the concept
of Quantity as simple unity of Discreteness and Continuity, but
also the idea that Kant had of four antinomies, as if that
number exhausts contradiction instead of the fact that every
single concept is in fact an antinomy. In attacking Kant's
CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON, the attack is on Kant for being
"apagogic" [SLI, p. 207; SLM, p. 193], that is to say,
assuming what is to be proved and thus repeating the assumption
in the conclusion. Hegel protests that Kant's proofs are "a
forced and useless tortuosity," "an advocate's
proof" [SLI, p. 208; SLM, p. 194], which sounds exactly as
if it says he is a "Philadelphia lawyer." He considers
the dialectic example of the old Eleatic school of thought as
superior to Kant, despite the fact that so much of actual
history had occurred since that period, which certainly should
have led to a more profound conception of dialectic.
Discreteness, like Continuity, is a moment of Quantity and in
fact it is only both moments, their unity that is, that produces
Quantum. At the same time, both in this chapter and in chapter
II on "Quantum," we sense Hegel's sharp distaste for
mathematical proof as being unworthy of philosophy, even though
at its start, in the theorems of Pythagoras, they were of the
essence, and there is no doubt also of their importance, and in
fact necessity, to Newtonian science and differential and
integral calculus. Although I know next to nothing of this, and
I am sure that modern mathematics which has reached into
economics, automation, and space science, that in essence all
that Hegel says here is inescapably true as is all that he says
on "Bad Infinity," and I dare say that any infinity
that is not human is bad....
Section Three: Measure
With the very first statement, "Abstractly the statement
may be made that in Measure, Quality and Quantity are
united" [SLI, p. 345; SLM, p. 327], Lenin once again
becomes excited and at the end of it, he makes all those
observations—Leaps! LEAPS! L E A P S ! [LCW 38, p. 123]. The
observation on Nodal Lines Lenin copies out nearly in full.
There is no doubt whatever that a transition from Quality into
Quantity as a leap, in opposition to the concept of any gradual
emergence, is the transition point for Lenin himself, breaking
with the old Lenin, not because the old Lenin was ever a
"gradualist," but because the OBJECTIVITY of these
leaps in ALL aspects of life is not anything merely quantitative
or merely qualitative, or as Hegel puts it: "The
gradualness of arising is based upon the ideas that that which
arises is already, sensibly or otherwise, ACTUALLY THERE, and is
imperceptible only on account of its smallness. . .
Understanding prefers to fancy identity and change to be of that
indifferent and external kind which applies to the
quantitative" [SLI, p. 390; SLM, p. 370].
To sharpen his own very different concept, Hegel goes over to
this question of gradual transition of Quantity to Quality in
Ethics, and says, "A more or less suffices to transgress
the limit of levity, where something quite different, namely,
crime, appears; and thus right passes over into wrong, and
virtue into vice" [SLI, p. 390; SLM, p. 371].
The third chapter of this section is called "The
Becoming of Essence" and is the transition, therefore, to
the Second Book [The Doctrine of Essence].
NOTES
- This refers to Marx's decision, made in the mid-1860s,
to place his polemics with various theoreticians in a
separate volume 4 of CAPITAL; it was published after his
death as THEORIES OF SURPLUS VALUE. See Dunayevskaya,
MARXISM AND FREEDOM, pp. 81-92.
- In German the paired terms idealism and ideality are
used more frequently than in English, in a sense
parallel to realism and reality.
- "Bad" or "spurious" infinity refers
to the condition in which a finite thing, in reaching
for infinity, becomes another finite thing, AD
INFINITUM, without ever reaching true universality.
- Irreducible, fundamental substances of the universe
according to Leibniz, of which the prime monad is God.
- The Eleatics were a school founded by Parmenides who
upheld a doctrine of monism wherein reality is one,
motionless, undifferentiated, and unchanging.
- The chief ancient Greek atomists were Democritus and
Epicurus, who held that reality is composed of
indeterminate particles called atoms, which acquire
determinacies such as color and shape only through their
interaction with human sense organs.
- In Hegel continuous magnitude is a quantity which
"propagates itself without negation...a context
which remains at one in itself" [SLI, p. 214; SLM,
p. 200]. Discrete magnitude is a quantity that is
noncontinuous or interrupted; it breaks up into "a
multitude of ones." The unity of both constitutes
the concept of quantity. "The fact that the
Hegelian structure could not be 'copied' by Marx, but
had to be re-created, does not mean that the Hegelian
structure for Hegel was wrong. On the contrary, he deals
with thought, and the logical form of the Universal
there is the Notion."
CLICK HERE TO GO BACK TO CONTENTS PAGE
CLICK HERE TO
SUBSCRIBE TO NEWS AND LETTERS |